Thursday, June 29, 2017

Appendix B. Experiments in synchronicity

Toward a signal model of perception
Synchronicity anecdotes

Please send corrections and comments to Krypto78@gmail.com

The experiments cited here must be regarded as little more than anecdotes. Not only do my temperament and circumstances make a rigorous experimental approach unfeasible, replicability is a big issue because of the variability of the proposed reality signals. As with the anecdotes of Appendix A, we cannot say that statistical analysis would reveal a non-random covert correlation.

Hopefully, more talented investigators will devise experiments that will be, if not altogether convincing, at least more suggestive than the results I have obtained. In fact, I have obtained a number of remarkable "manufactured synchronicities" in times past but either took no notes or lost them. What remains is, alas, not the strongest stuff.
Techniques for achieving a degree of control over reality projection are centered on belief and focus. However, the unconscious strongly influences these actions and so we may often find somewhat goofy synchronicities, as with Jung's "fish story" related in my main article.

The experimenter will be able to devise endless varieties of "interference" experiments but will find that if the pattern mix is overly complicated, the resulting phenomenon signal may very well show no noteworthy signs of blending, interference or coherence.

I have found, and anecdotal accounts from history tend to confirm, that the use of a mirror or mirrors can have a major impact on setting off a burst of similarly constructed reality subsignals. Also, it seemed plausible that visual symmetry might have import. Yet I wished to limit the number of variables. So in one set of experiments, I chose two- or three-digit numbers by a pseudorandom process; drew the resulting number and its mirror symmetry; and then placed a mirror before this inscription such that I viewed the inscription and its reflected image simultaneously. I also rocked the mirror because previous tests had indicated that that might add to the effect.

Though I cannot say why mirrors might be useful, it is notable that quantum effects are often associated with photon interference. I know that sounds like hocus-pocus, and I admit to feeling my way along here.

I decided to use low integers because of their simplicity, which I believed might reduce variability and because they usually (but not always) had a low E-value. I also wondered what might happen using prime numbers of low E-value.

Later I would pair a prime with a pattern carrying a relatively high E-value, again using the mirror process.

I qualitatively determined that when low E-values are used for every element of an image, the aftermath is usually unremarkable.

Eventually, I used a method I'd developed a while back of studying mathematics while keeping some images -- such as books -- on my desk. The synchronicities are easily as strong or stronger than anything done with mirrors. My thinking is that math study, which requires sharp concentration and focus, is effective in bringing about "echoes" from the images.

A note of caution is in order. Tinkering with the reality stream could easily yield unpleasant results, analagous to the manner in which LSD can bring on a bad experience. It may help to include in the experiment some image associated in the experimenter's memories with goodness. However, I cannot guarantee experimenter safety. Such experiments are akin to Ben Franklin touching a key during a lightning storm; he just got a bit of a tingle whereas an imitator was electrocuted.

Another note: the system crashed while I was working on this page, killing about two hours worth of work. When I went to rewrite the material, the notes concerning the segment at which I left off went missing, and remain so. There is no reason to think those notes were dropped or pilfered. I have omitted further discussion of that experiment (which was about nothing sinister or spectacular).

In retrospect, many of the "echoes" are anything but spectacular, but often my subjective impression at the time was that the echo "jumped out" at me, as if there was something strange or unusual about it. Clearly, though, one can always find a routine psychological explanation for such a sensitive reaction.

As of June 30, 2009, the final experiment on this page is dated June 3, 2009. In future, I will no doubt perform more experiments and include them on this or a related page. I likely will try to increase the E-value and, at least for a few tests, simplify the symbolism.

February 2008; day missing

I focused on this pair [31, RED] for less than a minute at about 3 p.m.

About 45 minutes later, I was in a local library and noticed a 12-year-old neighbor busy with a school project. She was doing some sort of survey and asked a fellow pupil: "What is your favorite color?" (The reply was inaudible.)

I had a sense that this was an echo. Victoria's question was about color, even if not red. And she was working on something numerically oriented, even if not specifically about the number 31.

Later, I went to stay at a friend's apartment and upon reaching the doorway, I noticed that the building number was 131. Of course there are 10!/8! = 90 permutations of two digits, giving a 1/90 chance of encountering the number 31. But there is also a 1/90 chance for any other two digits, so in probability terms, this is unspectacular.

Also, there was no particular echo of the color red in this observation.

Feb. 8, 2008

At about 5:30 p.m., I obtained the number 978 from the last three calculator digits for 51/2 and flexed a mirror in front of a symmetrical image composed of these digits.

The image took this general appearance


         9
         7
     9 7 8 7 9
         7
         9
except that the top two numbers were facing the other direction, as were the two right-most numbers.

As I was interested in checking a symmetrical design, I also drew the 8 as two circles and the 9's as a circle with a straight line segment tangent to it.

Later that evening I attended a seminar in which three very fine women reported on life-changing experiences. One speaker, who was one of seven siblings, described how her husband had died unexpectedly from three blood clots "in the lungs," though he had been taking Lipitor for high cholesterol.

Several echoes:

I tend to associate the numbers 9 and 78 with good things (a numerological idea I've picked up that I admit is hard to defend rationally). The women struck me as of especially fine character.

The two backward 9's were like P's, representing "pulmonary."

The 8 and the 9's looked like pills, representing the Lipitor.

Feb. 8, 2008

At 10:44 p.m. I chose the last two calculator digits for 110.71, which were 69.

This time I inscribed 6969 on a piece of paper, but had the second two digits facing the other direction.

I flexed the mirror about 10 times while looking at the figure and its reflected image.

After I had gone to bed, a teenage daughter of a close friend text-messaged me, asking that I fetch her some fast food. Her friend, a daughter of another close friend, also wanted food. (I had known both of them for years.)

I dropped off the food, and one of the girls, when she came downstairs, was a bit inappropriately attired (though not in her view). She told me her report card had two A's, three B's and three C's, a substantial improvement.

In our culture, of course, the number 69 is sexually suggestive. However, the incident was harmless.

I thought an echo had occurred because, though these girls were always asking little favors, the lateness of their call was a first.

There were other things I might report that could indicate echoes, but they are too nebulous to be worth detailing.

Feb. 11, 2008

At 10:02 a.m., the number 51 was chosen randomly from a book page. I inscribe 515 on a piece of paper with the last 5 facing the other direction and then rocked a mirror in front of the figure several times, using four rotations.

At about 11:30 a.m. I ran into a woman I know at a local library, a place I had never before seen her before. She had, unknown to me, recently moved into town with her husband and daughter.

I had used a book discarded by that library to select the "random" page number for my experiment.

Any other echoes, if any, are too nebulous to report.

Feb. 11, 2008

I first obtained 116, the last three calculator digits of the fifth root of pi. The prime decomposition of 116 is 2229 and so I used 29.

My notes record that a prime has an E-value for me because of my association of a prime with "hardness."

At 5:14 p.m., I inscribed on a piece of paper 2992, with the last two digits facing the other way and then put that paper in front of a large mirror. I then flexed a hand-held mirror in such a way that I could see the inscription in the hand-held mirror as reflected from the large mirror. I flexed the large mirror several times and also tried different positions for the hand-held.

During the mirror-flexing, I caught a glimpse of my abdomen and I wondered whether an echo concerning my belly or my body would occur.

After a nap, I went to the bathroom and found that a roommate had moved a sign reading "please wash out the shower, don't forget" to a spot under the mirror. The sign was intended for me.

I sense this as an echo though not a very pronounced one.

Later -- notes unclear about time -- I had to break an engagement with a friend set for the 19th because I had forgotten that I already had booked that date for another purpose. Apart from the number 9, there is little here.

Feb. 11, 2008

Unsatisfied with most results thus far, I tried another method in an attempt to get a more pronounced coincidence.
Using a pseudorandom process, I paired these two prime numbers thus:

(7)(19)

and then flexed the hand mirror about 15 times such that I could see the inscription doubly reflected, but stood aside so that very little of my image was seen.

The next day, there were several possible echoes but only one seems worthy of reporting. About 3 p.m., I read that Katherine Graham had been appointed publisher of the Washington Post. She was to report to her uncle, Post company CEO Donald Graham.

A "bit of me" is echoed here because I once served alongside Graham as an Army combat correspondent.

Weymouth and Graham are both "primes" in the Post company. Their family ties correspond to the pairing. Their independence is emphasized by the parentheses around the numbers. The ratio 7/19 approximates their age ratio.

Though these associations seem nebulous, at the time my subjective sense was that they were strong echoes.

Feb. 12, 2008

I flexed my hand mirror such that I could see reflections of this inscription:



E = ymc2
K = 1/2mv2
5,997
(The y was the Greek gamma.)

The number 5,997 was chosen by a pseudorandom process.

My thought was that perhaps the energy equations would have a higher E-value than mere numbers and hence yield a more pronounced coincidence.

I have notes concerning a possible echo in Abraham Pais's biography of Einstein, Subtle is the Lord, but I do not think it is worth including.

Feb. 12, 2008

I covered the back of the hand mirror with white paper, because I was concerned that its smoky design was muddying outcomes. At about 7:05 p.m., I flexed the mirror several times at an image I had taped to the wall. I am not sure what that image was, but was probably the inscription above.

I then held the mirror in front of the image and flexed it a few times in such a way that I couldn't see the reflection.

The following day, I spent most of the time in bed, sick with a cold. Checking my cell phone at one point, I found two text messages from one of the girls mentioned above. One was typical, asking that I bring her lunch to school (which I didn't, having been asleep). The other one was odd, asking if I had the number for Mr. Ice Cream.

I then realized that the white-backed mirror I had flexed looked rather like an ice cream cone.

I considered this coincidence to be a rather strong echo.

Feb. 18, 2008

By a pseudorandom process, I selected the prime 23 and performed a test with it. My notes of the test details are missing.

However, my notes record that sometime after 9 p.m. I was at a service organization meeting where various outreach opportunities were presented, including one for March 23. There was a short discussion about that date, as it was to fall on Easter.

This also seemed a rather pronounced emergence.

After this test, I ceased from experimenting with mirrors. Instead, I would put books with interesting titles on a table where I would study mathematics and check for rebounds. I have often done this in the past, getting numerous compelling echoes, but have no notes of those tests.

March 10, 2008

For an hour or two before 3:24 p.m. I did drill questions for second order differential equations. On the library table were these books: Just Six Numbers: The Deep Forces that Shape the Universe by Martin Reese and The Nine Numbers of the Cosmos by Michael Rowan Robinson. I only glanced at their content.
After finishing my study session, I checked the internet at saw that New York Governor Eliot Spitzer had been implicated in a prostitution ring. The numbers 6 and 9 (from the book titles) are, in American culture, considered sexually suggestive when written as 69. I recall thinking before checking the news that something sexy and maybe tawdry would show up as an echo. Interestingly, Spitzer was code-named "Client 9."

March 11, 2008

Did differential equations drills in the library between 11 a.m. and 1 p.m. or so. On the table were The Golden Ratio: The Story of the World's Most Astonishing Number by Mario Livio and The New Time Travelers: A Journey to the Frontiers of Physics by David Toomey. I glanced inside both books and sometime during my study session I noticed in Livio's book on the use of the number 666, which can be plugged in to a formula to get a close approximation of the negative of the golden ratio. I did some calculator manipulations but beyond that my notes are unclear.

In my mind, Middle Eastern events are often associated with the "number of the beast," because of the fact that much of the book of Revelation focuses on that region. The Iraq and Afghanistan wars, stemming from the insider atrocity known as the 9/11 attacks, make me think of the beast and the last days.

And so I saw an echo in the report that the top Middle Eastern commander had been fired for apparently emphasizing a moderate policy as opposed to the highly aggressive Bush-Cheney policy. The "666" is represented by the removal of a restraining hand.

As for any "time travel" or "golden ratio" echoes, my notes contain nothing worth reporting. This is not to say there are no echoes, but only that they are insufficiently pronounced to be useful.

March 12, 2008

At 1 p.m. I began to study differential equations with these books on the table: Infinite Ascent: A Short History of Mathematics by David Berlinski and A New Kind of Science by Stephen Wolfram.

I penciled in a cross inside NKS and took a brief look at Wolfram's cellular automata graphs (I had read most of the book some months earlier). Peeking inside Berlinski's book, I noticed he referred to NKS.

I noted a personal experience later that day but I think it unworthy to include, though I may reconsider in future.

However, the next day (time not noted) I read in the New York Times an obituary for the last French veteran of World War I. The cross in the "cellular automata" book is echoed by the fields of crosses in France and the low countries where the dead of World War I are buried. Armies reflect NKS's cellular automata and war reflects NKS's discussion of the mathematical topic of chaos theory.

French Premier Nikolas Sarkozy expressed "infinite sadness" in his tribute to Lazare Ponticelli, reflecting the "infinity" in the Berlinski book's title. That book also has the word "history" in its title, and the obituary concerns a momentous historical event.

The cross is also reflected in Ponticelli's comment on war. It is "stupid," he said. "You shoot at men who are fathers."

March 18, 2008

Sometime between 5 p.m. and 6:30 p.m. I was studying differential equations in a library. On the table were Extreme Waves by Craig B. Smith, showing on the cover a sailboat in peril; Blow the House Down, a novel by Robert Baer, a "bestselling N.Y. Times author"; Physics of Waves by William C. Elmore and Mark A. Head.

An orthodox Jewish man joined me at the table, where he placed three novels: The 5th Horseman, The Greatest Battle, and Sins of the Assassins. The first two were Apocalyptic fiction. He read from at least one of these books and also read the New York Times and the New York Sun.

About 10:45 p.m. the following day I read in the Times the obituary of Arthur C. Clarke, who wrote noted Apocalyptic science fiction novels. For example, Childhood's End features a race of aliens who look like devils.

Clarke was known for his efforts to steer humanity away from war, an echo of Sins of the Assassins. The writer had degrees in physics and mathematics, echoing the wave physics book and the math book. A scuba diving buff, he lived on Sri Lanka, which was struck by the devastating (almost Apocalyptic) tsunami of 2004. The Extreme Waves book discussed that tsunami, which killed 40,000 Sri Lankans.

Also, a very large rainstorm struck the central states today, causing massive flooding and killing 9 persons.

March 19 or 20, 2008

At about 6 p.m., I noted that I had been doing differential equation drills over the last 3 1/2 hours. I solved some easily but, because of mild fatigue, had difficulty with others.

On the table:

1. The Anchor Bible commentary on the gospel of John (I - XII), Volume 29, by Raymond E. Brown. I peeked at that and found it interesting.

2. General Relativity, an Einstein centenary collection of papers, S.W. Hawking and W. Israel, editors. The math looked difficult, I noted, but the book might be worth reading anyway.

3. Abstract Algebra by Lloyd R. Jaisingh and Frank Ayres Jr., a Schaum's Outline book (second edition).

Also on the table for a time was my folder full of math theorems, algorithms and formulae.

At any rate, during my study session, and after I had chosen the books, I got an email from a friend John telling me he was stranded in Atlantic City, several hours drive away, and needed a lift.

We fixed a time and place to meet the following morning.

The next day my breakfast and coffee was disrupted at a local eatery by a woman noisily complaining of having lost her wallet and wasting a trip. She then added that she'd been assaulted. I suspected that the high E-values imputed would have a negative affect during the day.

Echoes from the previous day: My friend "John" echoed in the book topic; perhaps my doing a Christian deed echoed in the book title; and "Atlantic City" echoed by the word "Anchor."

As it turned out, we missed each other at the casino and I wasted my trip. It later emerged that my friend had been assaulted and robbed of his wallet. So the woman's negativity echoed in these details.

My notes disclose nothing echoing relativity, other than the fact that we couldn't get our times and places to match up. Apparently, I was at one entrance and he at another, and when I went checking the other entrances, he was elsewhere.

My other notes concerning potential echoes concern things which are simply too nebulous to report.

March 26, 2008

Notes from March 25 are missing.

Mildly edited notes for March 26 have this to say:

"This morning I read on the New York Times front page a story about a new electronic fingerprint identification system introduced at a New York airport. Two Englishmen were interviewed, each with an opposing reaction. One, a businessman, had no problem with the testing; another, a writer, was offended by the intrusiveness.

"I remember thinking yesterday that an airplane echo was likely, since I wrote '7,127' and thought '727'."

The dualism of two prime numbers is reflected in the reporter's choice of two persons with contrasting views. Whether identification is also echoed is now unknown, my notes being lost.

April 22, 2008

I tried to study differential equations in the early afternoon, but was stymied by an allergy attack from accomplishing much. On the library table was the book Codes, Ciphers and Other Cryptic and Clandestine Communications by Fred B. Wrixson (Black Dog and Leventhal Publishers, 1998). Also on the table was a library survey form for April 12-27.

Later on I resumed study and placed on the table the book Star Wars Death Star by Michael Reaves and Steve Perry.

The next day, it was reported that a retired U.S. Army engineer had been accused of spying for Israel.

Espionage and counterespionage are strongly reflected in the title and the name Levanthol is Jewish, a link to the spy suspect, 87-year-old Ben-Ami Kadish, and the state of Israel. The spy case stemmed from the Star Wars era. There was a sudden supernova of exposure of a dark matter. The suspect couldn't have been far from death.

April 24, 2008

At 12:09 p.m., I noted that on the library table were The Invisible Man by H.G. Wells (a Tor Classic paperback); The Nomad of Time a three-novel collection by Michael Moorcock: The Warlord of the Air, The Land Leviathan and The Steel Tsar (Daw Books/Doubleday).

The Wells book concerns a man who takes a potion that makes him invisible and then into a psychotic killer. The Moorcock stories are about a former captain in the Royal Lancers who visits alternate realities.

I studied differential equations.

At 10:47 a.m. the following day, I noted: "re 'invisible man,' 'nomad of time' the echoes were either too personal or too nebulous to report." (I now don't recall, but I don't suppose they were anything terrible.)

April 25, 2008

At 11:38 a.m. I noted that I had leafed through Great American Deserts by Rowe Findley, photos by Wll? Meayers Edwards, National Geographic Society. I left that on the table while I was studying differential equations.

A note of 10:07 a.m. the next morning, recounts that the prior night was full of incidents of being deserted. By doing a favor for one of the teens mentioned above, I forsook an event that a friend had desired to attend with me. It was apparent that he felt deserted. The teenager, focused on her own agenda, deserted me without even a text message or phone call. Later, I realized I had told someone I would meet her at the event I had forsaken -- and hoped she didn't feel deserted. In sum, the evening turned out to be boring and lonely -- somewhat desert-like, that is.

Nov. 6 or 7, 2008

At about 3:30 p.m., I had on the library table the book The 23rd Cycle, which discusses solar flare activity.
I used my calculator to perform these operations:

(1 - 23-1 + 1 - 23-2)2 = 3.820583832
(1 + 23-1 + 1 + 23-2)2 = 4.18352732
               ----------
               8.004116624
I repeated the calculations and noted that the interval for these exercises was about 10 minutes. I then busied myself with other matters.

Later that day I wrote a bit of fluff on my blog about "number 23" whimsies (I have since deleted it).

At between 8 p.m. and 9 p.m. that day, an acquaintance told of a man whose son, only in his twenties, had just died. The man had overcome cancer as a teen, but it had recurred a year ago and had hit full force.

Comments: "Son" is a homonym for "sun." The cancer was a sonspot; the cancer flareup echoes the surge in sunspot activity, which goes in cycles. There was an eight- or nine-year interval between the cancer remission and flareup, echoing the sum between 8 and 9 calculated.

Prior to that, at roughly 6 p.m. and after my calculator exercise, a teenage girl sent me a text message reading "SON!", something she'd never done before or since. I checked the internet for a possible meaning and came up with "signing off now." As I recall, she later told me she'd intended that message for someone else."

Also, it should be noted that my reality formulation may have been influenced by the alleged "badness" of number 23, even though that was something I attempted to refute in my little blog post.
There is a break in my notes of about a year. I had done few experiments and hadn't bothered to record anything. I resumed recording results once I began to prepare to publish online Toward a signal model of perception.

April 13, 2009

On the 14th, I recalled that on the 13th I had been using scrap paper found in a trash container. On the printed side was some sort of legal document.

I was doing exercises in complex numbers, specifically trying to calculate 120.5 correctly, eventually getting it right.

During a walk, I happened upon an expensive graphing calculator, which I turned over to the university police. These happenings echo, of course, the slightly advanced math and the legal papers.

Later that evening, I was working out the complex number (1 + i)i and then (3 + 5i)i. My erroneous answers were 20.5/e and (34)0.5e-5i. Moments after arriving at the wrong answers, my young friend called to say that she was lost on Route 34. Shortly thereafter she was pulled over by a policeman for driving too slowly on that road. On the 14th, I noted, she told me she had also been robbed of her wallet, which contained $50.

The clearest echoes are the number 34 and the things going wrong, associated with my wrong calculation.

April 14, 2009

At 2:01 p.m., I wrote that I would use the back of scrap legal documents to do complex analysis drills, and that on my apartment desk I had placed a Bible and Dostoyevsky's Crime and Punishment.

About 4 p.m., I quit working. For an exercise, I worked on the solution to (9 + 11i)i, choosing the numerals because of high E-value and not specifically out of any desire to wreak mayhem.

I then turned on the television, where I watched a news story about a woman Sunday school teacher charged with raping and killing an eight-year-old girl. The woman wept at her arraignment.

The story had been running for several days, but this was the first I knew of it.

So we have these associations: legal papers --> law court, 9 and 11 --> a heinous act, Bible --> Sunday school teacher, Crime and Punishment --> the whole scenario, including the remorse of the killer.

Curiously, I didn't actually compute the correct answer.

Later that evening, I watched a snippet of Law and Order and noticed some echoes. But as the echoes are typical of TV melodrama I have decided to omit them.

However, I wrote, at 8:59 p.m. I returned to trying to correctly compute that quantity with the Bible and the Dostoyevsky book still in place.

I also tried to compute (9 + 11i)i(11 + 9i)i.

As soon as I ceased studying and turned on the TV, there was this return: A melodrama about a 12-year-old girl and Satanic stuff with a cop saying about some beastly thing: "The spell is real." I turned the TV off.

May 12, 2009

On the library table as I studied complex analysis during the afternoon were the books Hitler's Scientists by John Cornwall, Jungles of Randomness by Ivars Peterson and Coincidences, Chaos, All That Math Jazzby Burger and Starbird, and Elementary Differential Equations by Lyman M. Kells. Also on the table was the newspaper The Jewish State, a fairly militant publication.

About 5 p.m., I picked up the day's Wall Street Journal at the library and scanned a story at the bottom of page one raising the question of whether amateur gene-splicers posed a threat to national security. The headline included this phrase: "Let out your inner Frankenstein." Concern was expressed over the idea that genetic technology might fall into the hands of terrorists who might unleash some plague virus, but the experts quoted didn't seem very troubled.

We see the echo of evil in science here, possibly muted by the fact that I found the Hitler's Scientists book to be only mildly interesting. And any evocation of international terrorists carries with it the association of pro-Israel militancy.

Amateurs getting involved in gene-splicing might be construed as an echo of randomness. The probability of a catastrophe becomes so unpredictable as to be essentially random.

May 16, 2009

During the morning and afternoon I studied complex analysis, and on the library table I had placed Essential Topology by Martin D. Crossley (Springer) and Explorations in Topology: Map Coloring, Surfaces, and Knits by David Gay, both of which I glanced through, and Teach Yourself Sanskrit, a Complete Course for Beginners, which I also scanned.

On the table for a brief period was A Beautiful Math, a book about John Nash, game theory and the "quest for a code of nature." Also for a short time there was a flyer about local jazz and arts, which I put away.

At 6:59, my notes say, three women sharing a train compartment with me struck up a conversation about a woman who, on seeing her deceased husband's soul enter another body, swiftly marries this man.

This "random" chatter concerns transmigration of souls, a subject of the Upanishads and Rig-Veda. The Sanskrit book's stated intention was to help people to read these Indian writings in the ancient language.

At 7:57 p.m., my notes say, I had watched a public television travelogue, "Adventures with a Purpose," about the marvels of travel high in the Swiss Alps. I was struck by the intensity and vividness of the scenery and discussion. It occurred to me that topology might be thought of in terms of the cool climes of abstract spaces, and space was a very strong theme of this travelogue.

Sometime after I got off the train but before I watched this show, I stopped into the supermarket. One cashier, referring to a promotional gimmick, said to another: "You have to tell the people about the game we have." The response: "I don't know anything about that game." Then the clerk asked whether I wanted a game sheet and, on learning what it was about, I replied, "I'm not too interested."

It was only an hour or two later that I suddenly recalled that I had initially included the game theory book on the table, but then, thinking better of it, put it on another table. (Other experiences, which I have not chronicled, suggest that game theory can bring unpleasant echoes; also the more one uses for interference, the more probable a muddy result.)

I had visited this store often but, for me, the game materialized only that evening. After I brushed off the game theory book, a clerk and I each gave the game the brushoff.

May 19, 2009

The two topology books and the Sanskrit book mentioned in the previous segment were on the library table as I studied complex analysis, beginning at about 2 p.m.

At 10:14 that evening, I began a note concerning a NOVA special I had just watched: "Parallel Worlds/Parallel Lives," concerning Mark Everett, son of the late physicist Hugh Everett. An independent producer had prodded Mark, an alternative rock musician, to learn more about his dad and his dad's many worlds interpretation of quantum physics.

A lack of emotional bonding troubled the family, and so Mark, though he had loved his father, felt as though he hadn't really known him.

I must say that I wasn't very interested in the day's experiment and its symbolism and so perhaps the result wasn't quite as vivid in my mind as in the previous episode. In fact, I didn't look at those books that day. My emotional vacuum may have been echoed by the family's emotional vacuum.

Anyway, the many worlds scenario echoes the strange realm of topological spaces and also the astonishing worlds of the Indian classics. The parallel lives and worlds of father and son are echoed by the two topology texts.

The special included a scene of Mark looking at a string of math symbols which was counterpointed with his slowly gaining new insight about his father's work. We may regard this as an echo of the study of the strange-looking symbols of Sanskrit. His sister, it was reported, had killed herself in order to go to be with her father, also a possible echo of Indian theology.

May 20, 2009

On my apartment desk are two Bibles -- a King James version and a New American Standard version -- and the chilling chronicle, The War Against the Jews by Lucy S. Dawidowicz (Holt, Rhinehart and Winston; Bantam edition June 1976), which I read decades ago. Inside that book was a Catholic devotional card with a prayer to Michael and a painting of the archangel slaying Satan. My notes give the time of this observation as about 3:45 p.m.

Feeling a bit unwell, I was able to do only a few routine complex analysis problems, quitting at 4:59 p.m. Shortly before putting down the math book, my roommate had called out to invite me to watch what he thought would be an interesting movie; it was about pedophilia in the Catholic church in the 1960s.

At 11:27 that evening, I noted that the news program World Focus included a brief item about pedophilia and child abuse in Catholic institutions in Ireland. (The show is prepared before 6 p.m. daily.)

The next morning's New York Times contained a major story on the child abuse report. Another page one story was headlined "4 Accused of Bombing Plot at Bronx Synagogues." Another, "Lawyer's Ways Spelled Murder..." concerned a former prosecutor and defense attorney accused of suggesting that witnesses be murdered.

Echoes: Michael image and the Bibles --> struggle against evil in the church; Michael image in The War Against the Jews --> the plot to bomb synagogues averted; Michael slays Satan --> murderous lawyer exposed; also, implicitly, Hitler defeated.

June 2, 2009

I returned to my mirror method on this day. At 1:28 p.m., I wrote that I had taped to the wall the page one segment of a New York Times story headlined, "Plane Vanishes Carrying 228; Cause a Puzzle." Next to the story I inscribed the numbers 22.57, 225.3.11 and 2352. The first is the prime decomposition of 228 and the latter two stem from the numbers found in A330-200, the model number of the Airbus that vanished off Brazil.

I flexed a folding double hand mirror in front of the report, with the two mirrors at about a 45 degree angle or less.

I initially caught a glimpse of myself, but then mainly noticed two blobs of light playing over the type for about 30 seconds.

An hour or so later, my roommate returned and showed me a set of photos taken at a rustic retreat that we'd visited a few weeks previously. The pictures were almost all of trees, the lake, cabins and so forth. A very few pictures had familiar faces in them.

There may have been some minor echoes, but the most notable one was the matter of the missing people. There had been some 200 people at the conference but hardly any were in the photos. It would be days before a few bodies were recovered from the Atlantic; all others remain missing as of June 29, 2009. If the numbers had any echoes, they were insufficient to be worthy of notice.
June 3, 2009

The following was written on a piece of paper:
                 8
              71 + 17
                 8
Just after 2:14 p.m., I flashed the hand-held folding mirror in front of the inscription above, which I had taped to a wall in my apartment. I flexed the mirror in various ways, continually observing the reflection of the numbers.

Later, while sitting on a bench in a vest-pocket park I glanced at my cell phone and saw the time: 7:17; suddenly two girls emerged and were frolicking around the fountain of around a Civil War monument in front of me. Each appeared to be about 7 or 8 years old.

About a half hour later a friend gave me some phone numbers of some people I might need to be in touch with. I had trouble distinguishing her 8's from her 3's and had to ask her to verify an 8.

A bit later, someone else I know told me of newly discovered heart artery problems. I recall him mentioning that one artery had an 80 percent blockage.

A note of June 5, (may mean June 4) 2009, says that I checked the obituaries of David Carradine, who died June 4 in a Bangkok hotel. One story related that the 72-year-old had recently begun shooting a film (Stretch), which concerns a 17-year-old who publicly announced that he was going to kill himself before doing so.

Carradine's body was found hanging with a rope around his neck and genitals. Death apparently resulted from "auto-erotic asphyxiation."

Echoes: 71 --> age 72 (close but not exact); 17 --> age 17; two 8's symmetrically placed --> nooses about neck and genitals and suicide of 72-year-old and 17-year-old.

Now this may seem unpleasant, but let us recall the fine echoes of the two girls. The issue is not the creation of life or death, but the tuning in of reports. As an analogy, all sorts of things are broadcast on TV or via the internet, but one can't process all reports. Similarly, many "histories" are enfolded into reality, but only some are "energized" insofar as the observer is concerned.

Appendix A: anecdotal accounts of synchronicity

Toward a signal model of perception

Synchronicity 'experiments'

Posted June 25, 2009

Please send corrections and comments to Krypto78@gmail.com
Presented here is a collection of anecdotal accounts of what some may believe are episodes of synchronicity, along with my comments. I have not sought to arrange these accounts in any particular order.
We must frankly admit that none of these incidents could be shown, using standard statistical tools, to result of non-random covert connections.

Pauli's pull
The physicist George Gamow gave a humorous example of the Pauli effect in his book Thirty Years that Shook Physics (Dover reprint 1985):

"It is well known that theoretical physicists cannot handle experimental equipment; it breaks whenever they touch it. Pauli was such a good theoretical physicist that something usually broke in the lab whenever he merely stepped across the threshold. A mysterious event that did not seem at first to be connected with Pauli's presence once occurred in Professor J. Franck's laboratory in Gottingen. Early one afternoon, without apparent cause, a complicated apparatus for the study of atomic phenomena collapsed. Franck wrote humorously about this to Pauli at his Zurich address and, after some delay, received an answer in an envelope with a Danish stamp. Pauli wrote that he had gone to visit Bohr and at the time of the mishap in Franck's laboratory his train was stopped for a few minutes at the Gottingen railroad station. You may believe this anecdote or not, but there are many other observations concerning the reality of the Pauli effect!"

Similarly, the physicist Abraham Pais relates in his book Niels Bohr's Times (Oxford 1991), that Pauli was very proud of the "Pauli effect" whereby, beginning in 1922, "something would go wrong whenever he entered a laboratory." Pauli "would tell with glee how his friend Otto Stern, experimentalist at Hamburg, would consult him only through the closed door leading to his working space."

Wolfgang Pauli, a founder of quantum mechanics, seems to have come to believe in a phenomenon that his former therapist and friend, Carl Jung, dubbed "synchronicity," though he was careful about his phrasing.

His number came up

The novelist William S. Burroughs was fascinated by the number 23, recounts Robert Anton Wilson, a writer and mystic. "According to Burroughs, he had known a certain Captain Clark, around 1960 in Tangier, who once bragged that he had been sailing 23 years without an accident. That very day, Clark's ship had an accident that killed him and everybody else aboard. Furthermore, while Burroughs was thinking about this crude example of the irony of the gods that evening, a bulletin on the radio announced the crash of an airliner in Florida, USA. The pilot was another Captain Clark and the flight was Flight 23."

"Burroughs began collecting odd 23s after this gruesome synchronicity," Wilson wrote in the May 2007 issue of Fortean Times.

No scientist would consider Wilson, with his peculiar numerological theories, as a credible source, nor the Fortean Times as a reputable forum.

I have no interest in promoting any form of numerology, but I would say that such a scenario might reflect Burroughs' own mind. We don't know what he'd been thinking about or doing before this symmetrical coincidence set, but in our model reality signals at later times reflect interference of signals at an earlier time. The "meaningful coincidences" are similar subsignals triggered by a previous interference.

Traveling in Tennessee
One morning several years ago my son and I were driving from Knoxville in order to do some hiking in Tennessee mountain country. We had decided to take a scenic route and were barely aware that that route intersected a major interstate highway that linked to Knoxville. As we go to the intersection -- having slowed down after a wrong turn -- a man came down the embankment from the interstate. My son recognized him and we stopped to talk. The man, who my son had met with the day before, had had some difficulties and was hitch-hiking back to Ohio. My son was able to wish him well, say goodbye and give him some money for his journey.

I don't recall what the two of us had been discussing in the car, but I do recall thinking that that intersection of events was no random coincidence.

Safe conduct
A friend I have known for years recently confided this experience: He had gone with a group to go whitewater rafting in Pennsylvania. But there was no room for him on the raft and he rented a one-person kayak so he could accompany his friends.

When hitting some rapids, he capsized and spilled out of his vessel; his friends were nowhere in sight.

My friend is neurologically impaired and so was in quite a predicament, even though the water was not over his head.

At that point, a man appeared and from my friend's vantage point, "it looked like he was walking on water." The man helped my friend out of the stream and then took his leave. My friend was worried about the kayak, because ordinarily such an untended floatable shoots downstream. But, he turned and noticed it floating idly nearby.

My friend was clearly much taken with this experience.

My collage days
A few years ago I regularly indulged my artistic bent my artistic bent by composing collages in ways that I considered interesting and original.

On a number of occasions the "echoes" were quite strong, and occasionally gruesome. In fact, one collage was followed by an extraordinarily gruesome event that reflected the collage quite obviously (to me), and I have decided not to give details out of concern for the feelings of the survivors.

My thinking is that the juxtaposition of images that individually or collectively contain high E-values can have a profound impact on one's virtual world.

In fact, I became reluctant to make more of these and threw out almost all the ones I had made.

The collage technique underscores the interference effect. That is, the images form a superposed set, a collage, that influences the reality formulator, usually within 24 hours.

A cold day in hell

This could fit into the 'experiments' appendix, except that I was too irritable to consider what I was doing a detached experiment.

On the evening of January 23, 2009, I was in the San Diego Public Library glancing through a book on superconductivity, which occurs at extremes of cold. I noticed the word "transpire" used as a synonym for "occur" and was irritated at this unusual and unprofessional usage. In fact, I was so annoyed that I did "numerology" on the word and several anagrams of the word. But once the anger passed, I threw the paper with these scribblings in the trash bin.

The next morning, I encountered an internet story from the Independent about two young fishermen who survived shipwreck inside a floating icebox used for storing fish. They were enormously thirsty when rescued from the shark-infested South Pacific waters and had survived by drinking rainwater deposited by a typhoon that had failed to capsize their icebox.

Bad company
A year or two after the attacks of Sept. 11, 2001, I wrote a web page about the divisibility of numbers by a 9 or an 11.

The following summer afternoon I was enjoying a picnic put on by a spiritually inclined group. In the adjacent picnic grove was a gathering of members of the Pagans motorcycle gang, including women and children.

The Pagans are considered an outlaw gang and are known for their Nazi and occult symbolism.

They weren't raucous but rather subdued. They gave off "strange vibes."

My estimate is that the association that I and others have with the numbers 9 and 11 went into a reality projection of people who many, including myself, think of as engaging in evil.

I have noticed that when doing math, the projections, or "echoes," can be quite vivid.

Two Pied Pipers
When working on this page, I switched over to take a look at the news and noticed that Michael Jackson's heart had stopped and a short time later he was reported dead. I'm wondering if this sudden evil report is an echo of the "collage days" anecdote, which talks about the artist and gruesome happenings; in light of the singer's troubled public image, the Pagans anecdote might also have been a contributor.

After learning about Jackson's death, I stepped out of the library for a bite to eat and upon returning noticed a sign on the door advertising a rock performer who would sing for children that evening. The performer is a friend who is a member of the spiritually inclined group I was with at the picnic (though I don't recall that he was at the picnic). In fact, I later overheard some of his performance but did not attend.

The two singers who entertain children represent two spiritual paths offered in life, on the one hand represented by the hedonistic Pagans and on the other by the spiritually inclined group I was with (we like pleasure but strive against self-defeating pleasure).

Would all this mean that I think I caused a man's death? This type of thinking is akin to the questions that can and cannot properly be asked in quantum mechanics. The best that can be said is that the interference effects are followed by a possibly synchronistic report. The report very often is about an event that precedes the interference, just as would be expected in the discussion in my main article.

What do you know?
I had been studying differential equations the morning of April 23, 2009, and later jotted down a thought that impressed me taken from a book by Werner Heisenberg (Physics and beyond). He had written, according to my notes, that there were no determinants that could give the position of an emitted radium electron, that the quantum information gave all the knowledge there was.

Later, I visited a church where the speaker had the unusual first name, Knowledge.

I have many, many more personal anecdotes. But I don't have the notes of them and they are only randomly stored in my memory. So some of the more entertaining and perhaps compelling ones aren't here. If I happen to get around to it, I may add some more.

Toward a signal model of perception

Please send comments to krypto78 at gmail dot com
Apologies for the helter-skelter footnoting. Control F should should prove handy.


Contents:
Overview
Philosophy, time and motion
The issue of solipsism
Information, entropy and perception
Interpretations of quantum results
Abstraction and causality
Multiplexing possibilities
Feedback control
Goals and behavior
Reality construction
The importance of narrative continuity
Dreams and altered states of consciousness
Group reality construction
Randomness, probability and coincidence
Jung, Koestler and synchronicity
Appendix A: Synchronicity anecdotes
Appendix B: Synchronicity 'experiments'
By PAUL CONANT

Philosophy is perhaps the best category for this paper, which crosses the boundaries of various specialties. I have attempted to incorporate an interpretation of quantum phenomena into a still rough-hewn signal model of perception. Appendix B has results of experiments in the manufacture of unusual coincidences1x, which, not fulfilling rigorous experimental standards nor being classically replicable, are meant as food for thought.


There is a type of logic proof that gives a first approximation of the proof followed by one or more versions that hone and amplify the initial sketch. This paper does something of the sort, though no precise result is reached and certainly we are not aiming for any nail-on-the-head proofs. A principal reason for much of the fuzziness stems from the problem of defining terms, so many of which are interdependent or that have axiomatic roots that are hard to fathom. Even so, it is hoped that once the somewhat fuzzy pieces have been read, a larger Gestalt will emerge.

Disclaimer: Though I cite some of the ideas of such persons as Jung and Freud, I wish to make clear that I do not endorse any particular psycho-social theory, nor do I wish to revive old political controversies.

Overview
Though this paper intersects areas of philosophy, religion and mysticism, the main thrust concerns a perhaps plausible, communications-oriented model of perception. The model does not cope with all significant questions, just as Claude Shannon's information theory does not deal with the issue of meaning.

Our model focuses on signal interpretation and so, in a limited sense, touches on meaning, but effectively avoids the concept by making the interpretation of information a processing issue. Similarly, we sidestep a definition of consciousness, which we accept as axiomatic, though we do accept that there is a gradient of consciousness for each individual. Instead, we focus on how a human mind may cope with and, indeed, construct its reality. But ultimate reality is not our focus.

Though issues of psychology enter our discussion, we leave the lion's share of psychodynamics to others. Similarly, we avoid the minutiae of neuroscience. Our aim is to abstract a process, in the same vein as Turing's abstraction of a universal computer. Yet, we bypass most of the mathematics on the basis that most of the mathematical groundings are already well known.

A sketch of our line of thinking: the Schroedinger cat paradox demonstrates that "concrete" reality is far more ephemeral than is usually believed. In this sense Berkeley was right. Similarly, our intuitive sense of linear time biases our opinion as to what constitutes the perceived past and reality. The brain processes signals and manufactures a, for the most part, cohesive narrative which it perceives as "hard reality." But this reality is more dreamlike than is generally understood. Bizarre coincidences, or synchronicities, are a result of phenomenon wave interference.

Philosophy, time and motion
You're stuck with a grotesque and absurd illusion, the idea of time as an ever-rolling stream... There's one thing quite certain in this business: the idea of time as a steady progression from past to future is wrong. I know very well we feel this way about it subjectively. But we're victims of a confidence trick. -- Fred Hoyle1

Zeno, later fortified by Bishop Berkeley's criticism of differential calculus, has also told us that there is something distinctly odd about time and motion. Some may believe that Karl Weierstrass's epsilon-delta proofs of mathematical limits have neutralized these issues, but of course the enigmatic nature of time and motion has resurfaced with the theory of relativity and with quantum mechanics.

Physicist Alan Lightman2 makes the point that the quantum energy limit means that if one raises a swing to a particular height Y, the potential energy is nh, with n an integer and h Planck's energy constant. So our idea that we may raise the swing to any height between 0 and Y is wrong. Yes, the gap between allowed energies corresponds to changes in height of about 10-33 inch, but we still have the question, what happens to the swing between n and n+1? Apparently, it does not exist in an intuitive sense. The swing (or some small region on it) exists in a frozen state (instantaneously) for each allowed height. At the next height, the swing region miraculously appears again. There is no transition between n and n+1!

One is of course reminded of how motion pictures work, with slightly different still frames run together to form a smooth impression of something we call motion.

So Zeno had a point. One never really crosses a distance measured in terms of the real number line. One crosses a Planck distance measured in integers only. But then Newton had a point. The derivative, or fluxion, represents instantaneous time. That is to say, the duration of the time interval is zero, and this mathematical concept has been to some extent confirmed by quantum mechanics (though for strict rigor, if not in practice, quantum mechanics requires the use of finite difference calculus). Actually, 0 is also an enigmatic concept in quantum theory, whereby we are faced with quantum limits on the definition of time and distance which are, of course, interdependent with the notion of energy.

There are, of course, many more puzzles concerning quantum phenomena and time, such as Alain Aspect's validation of Bell's inequality, a sensational result that has stirred no end of wrangling but which assuredly points to a difficulty with coming to terms with the concepts of time and history.

Suppose we have two detectors A and B where A is closer to the source of an entangled pair than B. The observer looks at B and finds that, say, the result is "spin up," implying that -- ignoring the possibility of error -- detector A must say "spin down." But if A's state is in superposition until observed, then so is B's. Yet once A is looked at, B's result is determined. Yet the particle, according to the classical view, arrived at A before its partner arrived at B. Some have argued that the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen problem implies instantaneous, faster-than-light messaging between the detectors. But in this scenario, if a message is sent from A to B, the implication is that it went backward in time.

Following John Archibald Wheeler, we have the scenario of a photon that had a, say 50-50 probability of taking a clockwise or counterclockwise hyperbolic curve around a gravitational-lensing star. That star might be billions of light-years distant. So did the observation of the photon determine an event that occurred billions of years ago?

Or consider the wrinkles in the cosmic background radiation, which are supposed to have been a consequence of quantum fluctuations more than 13 billion years ago. These erratic fluctuations are credited with the irregularities that eventually led to formation of stars, galaxies and life on earth. Yet such "fluctuations" are a consequence of observation. Had the wrinkles been detected on some other day, a very different observable universe would presumably be seen. Maybe the moon wouldn't be there, after all. Yet, somehow the wrinkles have become "concrete-ized" so that different observers will fairly well agree that they are about the same whenever and wherever observed, much like the moon.

Asked whether the observer influences the observed object, Wheeler replied, "The observer does not influence the past. Instead, by his choice of question, he decides about what feature of the object he shall have the right to make a clear statement."3

In his autobiography, Wheeler writes that measurement of the photon "in some sense determined that history" but that a measurement is a mechanical registration not requiring a conscious observer.3a

This almost seems like a quibble. From the perspective of the observer, only one history becomes available once a question is asked and answered by "collapse of the wave function."

So if an entangled message was not sent via Einsteinian spacetime, what is the correct description? I do not propose a full answer to the question except to say that bilocalism seems to imply a cosmic fabric that is deeper than our usual phenomenal belief system. Nobelist Brian Josephson (Google his home page for link to paper) has argued that quantum bilocalism might well be linked to the bilocalism of paranormal events, an idea that has made him a most unwelcome presence in some scientific quarters.

Then we have Einstein's discoveries that time is a function of velocity (in special relativity) or, actually, acceleration (in general relativity) and his overthrow of simultaneity, a necessary idea in Newton's background frame of "equably flowing" time. (Newton, by the way, strongly suspected that there was more to the world than what he described in Principia, and spent much of his life as an alchemist seeking to unravel the mysteries behind the world of phenomena.)

Einstein's friend, Kurt Goedel, found a set of solutions to the differential equations of general relativity in which it was in principle possible to go forward into the past. Einstein, while not disputing Goedel, wondered whether such solutions had any relation to physical reality. But Goedel was convinced that if one solution of Einstein's field equations showed such a result, then there was a disturbing problem with the conception of the lapse of time, even if we don't actually live in such a universe.g After all, he noted, whether closed time-like loops exist would only depend on the arrangement of mass in the cosmos. We might add, why should a cosmos exist with such an anthropomorphic preference?

If both Goedel and Einstein are correct, then should we not be prepared to construe time as a perceptual matter?

This point is underscored by Feynmann and others who considered that particles can and do "travel backward" in time. If so, can time be said to exist at all?

Reflecting Hermann Minkowski's definition of a light year as equal to i second, Stephen Hawking has argued for "imaginary" time. All complex numbers on the plane can be mapped onto a sphere with the north pole point representing the point at infinity on the plane. Might not time behave similarly, whereby the closer one gets to the finite beginning of time, the closer one gets to eternity?

Consider the matter of metabolic rate and awareness. In some sense, a fly is certainly aware of its surroundings. But what is its now? It lives fast and dies soon, by comparison with a human, whose now is much longer. A being who is much larger and slower than a human would presumably regard the human now as amusingly short. Further, what would a being of cosmic scale regard as now? Might not such a now be immensely long, possibly even eternal?

This said, we should acknowledge that the sense of now is of course limited by the quantum limit on time subdivision and it seems plausible that it is a peculiar function of consciousness. A percept, in the sense of a small process that precedes and includes consciousness, would be a kernel of this now, I suppose.

In fact, neuroscience experiments have determined that direct, unitary perception of an event "now" lasts between 0.02 and 2 seconds. For visual experience, the percept or "now" length is about 0.01 s, for auditory experience the duration is about 0.02 s. A continuous sensory stimulus lasts no more than 1.5 to 2 s.

Admittedly, we have not properly defined now. But the point is that what we call time is closely related to perception, and we are faced with a form of the chicken-or-the-egg problem.

All this is well-known, but it in fact runs counter to the intuitive sensibilities of many scientists. They know of these disturbing issues, but most of their bread-and-butter work involves standard "equably flowing" time and they brush aside questions concerning causality as matters of interpretation that can be dispensed with. (For an acute discussion of the problem of perception as it relates to a sense-based input datum, see Bertrand Russell's The Analysis of Matterzz2. Russell is skeptical here of the standard "scientific materialism" of his day.)

Yet this prejudice may hinder alternative ways of discussing physical reality, ways that in fact evoke strong, and occasionally irrational, protest.3b

The issue of solipsism
"Inconsistency," it has been said, "is the hobgoblin of small minds." But without that concept, logic, mathematics and science in general would not exist. Scientists prize consistency and tend to disdain the self-referencing problems of Russell, Goedel and Turing.

Even so, Goedel's incompleteness theorem tells us that our ability to analyze has limits. But within those limits, scientists have tended to favor linear formulae, such as those of Newton, because they give a good measure of predictability. Whenever feasible, non-linear systems are approximated with linear equations. Yet, as systems become more complex, predictability tends to decline and non-linear feedback reigns. Chaos theory and results from catastrophe theory show that non-linear systems can evolve toward fundamental unpredictability (the noise amplitude equals or exceeds the desired signal), supercomputers notwithstanding.
It is non-controversial that perceived reality is influenced by the brain's processing routines. But to what degree is that reality dependent on the brain? If it is "too much," then can we say that some absolute, equably evolving, external background frame of reality (or information) exists?

Solipsism is the notion that the only certifiable reality is what one's mind entertains, which contrasts with the scientific tradition of categorizing working sets of abstractions that are independent of any one mind. Hence, there is a strong bias among scientists in favor of an absolute background reality. An altered state of consciousness is viewed as a pathology related to mental illness, brain damage, drug use, extreme emotional stress, fatigue or sensory deprivation.

Russell rebuts strict solipsism by observing that "reading a book is a very different experience from composing one; yet, if I were a solipsist I should have to suppose that I had composed the works of Newton and Shakespeare and Einstein, since they have entered into my experience," He adds, "Seeing how much better they are than my own books, and how much less labour they have cost me, I have been foolish to spend so much time composing with the pen rather than with the eye."zz2

Yet the fact that fear (the root of much mental illness), brain damage or some extreme psychic disturbance can completely derange "reality," might give us some insight into the "normal waking state." In both normal and abnormal cognitive states, the brain is processing and decoding signals via a sophisticated negative feedback control system (though some acute episodes of mental dysfunction are a consequence of the emergence of positive feedback).

To a great extent, students of neuroscience and perception have found that much, if not all, of perceived "reality" is manufactured. If we think of "reality" as a data stream strongly influenced by the interaction of a scanning device with the environment (while conceding, in line with Chomsky, that some of the "core reality" is hard-wired), the distinction between "normal" and "abnormal" perception boils down to the sentient being's success at survival and, perhaps, procreation.

In his book About Time, Paul Davies4 raises the solipsism issue: "In fact, how can we be sure that the universe wasn't created a hundred years ago, with everything arranged to appear as if it were much older. Or, for that matter, perhaps the world started five minutes ago, and we were all made with consistent memories of our earlier activities [planted?] in our brains. Even more interesting would be if our memories varied a bit, to inflame controversies like the number of gunmen who killed President Kennedy."

This last point is of some interest. We would expect that slightly different reality histories would clash. The question is, is there an "actual reality" against which the conflicting memories can be matched? Or are attempts at forensic inquiry fatally tainted because investigation brings about new realities (or histories)? Essentially, what we would like to know is whether a set of absolute truths -- an equably flowing absolute background reality -- exists and, if so, what form it takes. It would seem that some such absolute system is necessary, but there is no guarantee that it will be the background reality implicitly assumed by most physicists.

As an analogue, let us consider Einstein's belief that phenomenal reality suffices in terms of a computer terminal screen. Suppose we have some very smart people from a lost Pacific island who, for the first time, encounter a modern computer terminal that is showing a group of videos. The keyboard is missing. They examine the imagery and postulate various rules for the behavior of the phenomena. Fine. But what is the chance they will be able to work out the deeper reality of the electronic system running the program from simply viewing the screen's videos?

Nonlinearity comes into play here. As individuals interact and exchange information, we might expect their perceptions of "past events" would tend to merge. Still, I am uncomfortable with the idea that reality is so malleable that it is pointless to wonder about government conspiracies. But that's only personal prejudice, of course.

We are dealing with a matter of degree. We cannot rule out that some knowledgeable observers are not in denial about the circumstances of JFK's death or the attacks of 9/11, but are actually living in some other world that somehow interacts with your world and mine. (Even so, I feel quite certain that denial -- repression of unwelcome truths -- is a common psychological phenomenon greatly exploited by political elites.)

Information, entropy and perception
We can accept Shannon's definition of information as the negative of the log of the probability of the detection of some symbol and his associated definition of entropy as pi-1log pi, where Ã¥ i pi = 1

An oft-unnoticed implication here is that a message requires some form of control in order to counteract noise, which is to say entropy. A message conveyed through a sequence of signaling systems will degrade over time (as the childhood game of "telephone" should convince us). In other words, if information is to be retained, energy, directed into error-correcting codes and algorithms, must be continually added to the transmission system. This, of course, dovetails nicely with the entropy and conservation laws of thermodynamics.

Sometimes we might like to be sure that some information string is not only of relatively low probability, but reflects what we sometimes loosely call order. The string 010101... may be of low probability and yet constitute a message of low value. A means around this would be to append the information in the error-correction code to the information in the message.

The inclusion of error-correction information then leads us to accept that information is really a mental construct, even if that construct is common to a number of minds. Information requires work, which we account for via the error-correction process. In fact, though work is defined as equivalent to energy (W = K = 1/2mv2), my thinking is that the difference between the two is that work carries with it a higher level of information than does energy in general. That is to say, some of the energy of the system goes into what might be called an error-correcting process. This diversion of energy, coupled with the First Law of Thermodynamics, then accounts for the Zeroth Law that rules out perpetual motion machines for high-variable systems.

(Nevertheless, if we cast work in terms of efficiency, then work of low efficiency implies high entropy -- and as for the impossibility of a perpetual motion engine, this applies to a repetition of a high-information state, which is extraordinarily improbable.)

So the tendency toward increased entropy implies that information -- viewed as a transmitted or stored message -- is time-dependent. In fact, the concept is, like energy, an abstraction of a process that to a great extent depends on activities of the brain.


NOTE: From a classical perspective, Boltzmann entropy, Shannon entropy and the "arrow of time" can be reconciled thus: We consider a dynamical system at some time t0 to be represented by a single net force vector. In the case of a gas in a sealed container, the vector is close to 0. This vector is the sum of all the constituent force vectors at t0. (We can also notionally calculate from ta to tb.)

For even mildly complicated systems, the information in the net vector V is insufficient to tell us which "path" brought about V. That is to say, V is the sum of all other force vectors and we cannot know the order of summation. Hence, we say that entropy has increased and reversibility is impossible.

In quantum terms, the arrow of time -- to wit, irreversibility -- follows from the general non-commutability of matrices in matrix mechanics. The few cases where AB = BA represent the relatively rare symmetrical systems.
In addition, broken symmetry occurs at the particle level, whereby violation of geometric parity implies a noncommutative relation.


This viewpoint would appear to accord well with Neils Bohr's position that knowledge of quantum events is limited to the questions we are able to ask, though Bohr was anxious to disentangle the macro-world from quantum weirdness.

Wheeler has said that the cosmos cannot be a giant machine ruled by any pre-established continuum law.

Please see my paper

On Hilbert's sixth problem
https://cosmosis101.blogspot.com/2017/07/on-hilberts-sixth-problem-and-boolean.html

That is to say, Wheeler would seem to suggest that he does not favor the idea that the universe can be expressed as a sum of units of information.

One of the issues when it comes to perception is that the entropy law implies that mental constructs, or phenomenon signals and memories, fade or fail. Their tendency toward extinction is, we suggest, based on the emotion level attached to these constructs, a point discussed below.

This E-value corresponds to the strength of the error-correction code, even though a strong E-value might induce what is construed to be memory distortion.

The entropy of the brain's programs, such as memory templates that fade out if not reinforced, is an obvious consequence of natural systems. In an imperfectly conducting cable -- or set of circuits -- sine waves of different frequencies travel at slightly different velocities, yielding delay distortion, a smearing out of the wave packet and its form. In other words, virtually any signal tends to get noisier and noisier over time simply as a result of its principal media.

Interpretation of quantum results
I well realize that the term interpretation has become a catch-all means of evading the logical implications of material acausality and bilocalism, as if interpretation is a matter to be left to philosophers, mystics, poets and cranks. If one is interested in mere brute-force calculation, then this view will serve. But recall that Einstein was highly interested in interpretation in his 1905 relativity paper. In fact, his interpretation of physical reality so as to exclude an ether is among the things that distinguish his relativity paper from Poincare's 1904 paper and a reason why he, not Poincare, is honored for the breakthrough. The wrong interpretation was impeding scientific insight. In a similar vein, Einstein's theory of gravity reinterprets the physical description of space.

Suppose for the moment that we divorce conscious awareness from the cosmos. Then one might say that the cosmos just is -- no causes, no effects, just an undifferentiated whole. (This still isn't quite right, there being no observer to make this appraisal.) This whole is sometimes called a spacetime block. Without the mind to experience motion, there is no distance and no time. Moreover, if we think in terms of a manifold of greater than 3+t dimensions, the block, taken as a whole, is frozen.

So let us consider the three principal interpretations of quantum reality:

1. Copenhagen. Bohr favored the concept of limits to knowledge. There is no explanation of the counterintuitive results of quantum mechanics and so we must only talk about the results of measurements of quantum phenomena. The "question" strongly influences the result.8a This approach helped him avoid public discussion of strange implications, such as were brought to the fore by Schroedinger's compelling thought experiment.

2. John Von Neumann's observer centrality. Von Neumann argued that there is a chain of quantum events between the measuring device and the brain and so the "collapse of the wave function" occurs in the central nervous system and hence the observer is the key to quantum phenomena. Schroedinger introduced his cat specifically to underscore the absurdity of this idea, but the experiments of Aspect confirming Bell's inequalities leave room for puzzlement.

3. Many worlds. There are several variants of Hugh Everett's "many worlds" proposal, which says that the superposition of quantum states implies that there are numerous branching realities, or universes, that evolve for each quantum event. Bohr's reaction to this idea froze Everett out of academic physics. Murray Gell-Mann, who proposed a variant he called "many histories," like Schroedinger, wished to show the absurdity of observer centrality by pointing out that an ancient crystal could show a track from a quantum particle. Would not this imply that the observer had somehow formulated this implicit history by simply looking at the crystal?

Wheeler has pointed out that a quasar billions of light years out is seen in two positions because of gravitational lensing of an interposing galaxy. If one uses a detector to observe a single photon, would not that imply that the photon's trajectory to the left or right of the quasar was determined by the observer, even though the galaxy is hundreds of millions of light years away?

Interestingly, when Bohr, Max Born and Wolfgang Pauli defended the Copenhagen interpretation and strongly criticized Einstein's "hidden variables" belief (a phrase none used but which succinctly describes Einstein's position), Einstein retorted by pointing out that the Schroedinger thought experiment (Einstein substituted a mechanical recorder for the cat) scaled up quantum weirdness into the macroscopic world, something he thought to be unacceptable though not logically impossible.e

[I need to insert here that Pauli's position as of 1949 that what is now called the Copenhagen interpretation is completely satisfactory should be taken into account when discussing his apparent sympathy with Carl Jung's notion of synchronicity.]

Consider this scenario:
A human DNA mutation may occur when a high-energy particle collides with chromosomes, causing a rewriting of the stored information. Hence, cosmic rays, nuclear reactor leaks or even sunlight photons can cause mutations. Quantum rules are used to describe all these particles and their detections.

Now suppose a person -- absent any medical or family-history reason -- decides to be tested for a hereditary disorder. According to the Von Neumann postulate, the collapse of the dangerous particle's wave function doesn't occur until he or she reads or hears the result of the test. Prior to that detection, the photon was in a superposed state and cannot have been said to have interacted with the chromosome of some ancestor.

I once posed this conundrum to a physicist who had written a popular article and he replied that such an absurdity was why he subscribed to the decoherence arguments propounded by David Lindley.5 He then begged off further correspondence, telling me that he had recently discovered that he had a hereditary disorder.

Interestingly, Wheeler, who spurns the need for a conscious observer as a determinant of history, nowhere in his autobiography mentions the Schroedinger cat thought experiment.

At this juncture, I would like to address a point of confusion that has entered into the debate. According to some, the rapid decoherence of the waves constituting macro-phenomena implies that Schroedinger's cat is only in a live/dead superposition for a very short, effectively unobservable time, and so there is no real measurement problem for large objects.

Two points:

1. As SQUID experiments and experiments with large molecules have shown, it is possible to obtain superposed states of quantum phenomena in relatively large systems, which are detected by indirect means. Or consider the Bose-Einstein condensates, whereby a group of atoms is superposed and only a single superposed state can be said to exist. So the principle is established that alternate "realities" do indeed coexist even if such systems tend to entangle with the ambient environment and decohere rapidly.

2. Schroedinger was addressing the issue of what is a detector and what is an observation. When does the observation occur? Some have tried to argue that the measurement occurs once the cat dies, or doesn't, or at the moment that the box lid is opened.

Let us, however, consider a cloud chamber or scintillator track of a quantum particle. What do we see? A sequence of water droplets formed around the ionized atoms, where the least squares method gives the particle's fictional "continuous" trajectory. Each droplet is correlated with a quantum action (movement of a valence electron) that was emitted by an atom that was "close enough" to the transient particle for an energy exchange. Because the atoms are jiggling about, the sequence of blobs is irregular. If it were possible to fire another particle with the same energy and precision (not possible), we would see a different path, because atoms would not reliably intersect in the same places with the particle.

Now consider what happens as we look at a quantum measurement. There is a sequence of intermediate quantum events. So in most cases there is some very large number of quantum paths between the "external" detection and the brain's cognition. So each leg of each path is in superposition at the micro-level. We may then regard each path as in superposition with all the other paths. In other words, our interaction with the measurement requires a set of superpositions of states. Yes, this set of superpositions doesn't last long, but we haven't got rid of the cat conundrum by appeal to "decoherence." There is actually a large set of live states and another large set of dead states that link to the observer's consciousness.
Related to the decoherence viewpoint is the ensemble argument which says that quantum events can only be assessed statistically. One simply does not ask about the cat's state before observation.

But if one does wonder about the cat's state when one is not looking, the implication is that all these quantum paths to the cat are untaken and so in superposition. If we choose to think in terms of linear time, then the state of the unobserved cat is bothersome. But, if we accept that time is not some sort of equably flowing river, then perhaps we can accept the implication that phenomenal reality is not so "concrete" as one might think.

Bohr's interpretation essentially required that a sharp distinction be drawn between the experimental apparatus and the observer, but such a program doesn't really work. As Bell said, "The problem of measurement and the observer is the problem of where measurement begins and ends, and where the observer begins and ends. Consider my spectacles, for example: if I take them off now, how far away must I put them before they are part of the object rather than part of the observer? There are problems like this all the way from the retina through the optic nerve to the brain and so on." (Quoted in The Ghost in the Atom, P.C.W. Davies, J.R. Brown, ed, Cambridge 1986.)

It should be noted that Bohr's thinking evolved over time, but when he took into account the observer, it was as a way of saying that the lack of distinction between observer and observed limited what we can know about the physical world. "There is no quantum world. There is only an abstract quantum physical description. It is wrong to think that the task of physics is to find out how nature is. Physics concerns what we can say about nature," Bohr is reportedP2 to have said.

As Bell notes in Ghost in the Atom, Aspect's finding of strong correlation for entangled pairs makes the measurement problem harder "because Einstein's view that behind the quantum world lies a familiar classical world was a possible (and now discarded) way of solving the measurement problem -- a way of reducing the observer to an incidental role in the physical world.

Similarly, Pascual Jordan said that "observations not only disturb what has been measured, they produce it."6

Questioned about whether some inanimate device could replace a mind in a quantum measurement, Rudolph Peierls responded in the negative.6a A quantum experiment "goes on until you can throw away one possibility and keep only the other" which is when "you finally become conscious of the fact that the experiment has given one result."

Peierls insisted that "there is a quality of human beings, call it mind, that distinguishes us from the other objects in our environment and which is absolutely crucial for making sense of fundamental physics."

As Nick Herbert7 said of the Von Neumann interpretation, "In Von Neumann's consciousness-created world, things (or at least their dynamic attributes), do not exist until some mind actually perceives them, a rather drastic conclusion but one to which this great mathematician was forced by sheer logic once he had decided to take the quantum measurement problem seriously.

Eugene Wigner's view8 was that conscious reality is absolute and that physical reality is dependent on conscious reality.

Consider the case of Wigner's friend. Suppose Wigner sets up a quantum measurement and is prepared to see whether a particle is, say, spin up or spin down. Under Von Neumann's postulate, the superposition remains until Wigner actually looks at the detector. But suppose Wigner is in the next room and calls out to his friend to look at the detector and shout out the result of the experiment. Is the friend in a superposed state until Wigner hears the answer?

In his book Physics and Philosophy (Dover reprint of 1946 title), James Jeans concludes that the debate over whether material phenomena are mental forms or whether mental forms are a consequence of material phenomena seems to be leaning toward the former. He once said that "the universe begins to look more like a great thought than like a great machine."1y

Fred Hoyle, the British astrophysicist, was another backer of Von Neumann observer-centrality, arguing that the attempt to separate the macro and micro worlds via statistics wouldn't always work. His variant of the Schroedinger cat scenario was a bomb rigged to a quantum device. If one doesn't look at the device, presumably the bomb both explodes and doesn't explode. This, he insisted, means that consciousness is crucial to reality.8b

The many worlds interpretation might be construed as an attempt to bring some external background reality back into science and dispose of the distasteful subjectivity implicit in observer-formed reality. But this interpretation has its own problems.

David Deutsch has defended his "weakly interfering" many worlds view by saying that, with the entire universe described as a wave equation, there is no longer a need for strong subjectivity in quantum theory. Hawkings, by positing a no-boundary universe (roughly analagous to a Mobius band, perhaps), suggested that the wave equation description could be adopted with "initial conditions" being similar to the point at infinity on the complex sphere's projection onto the complex plane. Hawkings also seems to favor demoting the observer to minor status.

What bothers Seth Lloyd about the many worlds interpretation is his experiential reality of the ego as the center of the universe. A backer of Gell-Mann's many histories idea, Lloyd finds it troublesome that there would be many variants of himself in split-off universes, but Deutsch responds that these split-off universes do not strongly interfere and so there is no need for concern. (See Lloyd's home page to read the Lloyd-Deutsch debate.)

Topologist Jim Conant has pointed out that the many worlds scenario means that there is one world in which an individual has missed every life-threatening accident of nature as opposed to all his fellows, who have not survived. This person would live alone indefinitely in one of these universes. Though we will not use the "obviously silly" argument to dispute this interpretation, surely such a scenario raises significant philosophical issues.

Commenting on the Schroedinger cat problem, Leonard Susskind9 asserts that the only way to avoid the difficulty of wave function collapse "is to include the entire observable universe as well as the branches of the wave function in the quantum description." Susskind favors a multi-bubble-universe model.

But Rolf Landauer opposes such a view. "We caution those who invoke the wave function of the universe. How can that wave function be recorded, unless you have a second and separate universe available for that?"10 So there would need to be an infinity of Susskind bubbles and the ultimate recorder would never be reached.

David Bohm, who struggled to find some form of classical causation in quantum theory, eventually settled on the analogy of the hologram to describe his notion of "implicate order," whereby a hidden process might be behind seemingly strange results.11 His "quantum potential" permitted instantaneous signaling, which brings the notions of space and time into question.

Bohr emphasized the concept of "complementarity," as in the wave complementing the particle. From what I can gather, he perhaps means "two sides of the same coin." Or, perhaps he was suggesting something like interdependence of definitions. For example, Euclid gives us a line in terms of points or points in terms of a line. They strictly imply each other.

Similarly, we might view complementarity to mean that clashing concepts result because A <--> B. Notice that when A <--> B we cannot say A causes B or the converse.

When A <--> ~A, of course, we have an inconsistent system. This doesn't, however, hold for waves and particles because we say that detection of A --> no detection of ~A (detection of a wave implies a particle hasn't been detected), though we don't have a visualizable picture of why the types of detection differ.

Abraham Pais reportsP1 that Bohr thought of complementarity as akin to two Riemann surfaces, a concept he encountered in a course on complex analysis. We can see that Bohr was thinking topologically, in the sense that two Riemann surfaces reconcile related but mutually exclusive mathematical objects.

Interestingly, Einstein used Riemann topology for his general theory of relativity, but apparently did not grasp how Riemannian concepts could undermine the principle of causality. On the other hand, Bohr's intuitive topology is essentially a heuristic device.

To paraphrase Bohr, we might say that complementarity is akin to two branches separated by a branch cut. Sometimes the cut is placed at a singularity. So z-1/2 has two branches with a singularity at z = 0. We might suggest the singularity brings to mind the unobservable component whereby wave and particle are somehow fused in an undefined way.

Though this is an interesting analogy, we should caution that plenty of situations have multiple branches. For example, ln(z) has an infinity of branches (because ln(z) = 2i(p+ k), where k is any integer). Similar analogies can be made for Riemann surfaces.

Of course, the usual meaning of complement is expressed symbolically: Ac = A\B where B is a subset of A. This equation expresses dualism nicely but is trivial in terms of causality or acausality.

To be blunt, complementarity strikes this writer as so much hand-waving.

Abstraction and causality
When we say that A causes B, what do we mean? Ordinarily we mean that phenomenon A, or, better, signal A is linearly associated with B in time (A reliably occurs before B). If A is an input into the brain processor, there is an inference that B will be a following input.

We might regard this as a black box scenario. Input of signal A into the box is expected to be followed by the output of signal B. Yet, if we decide to look inside the black box, we will find another black box. The notion of scientific advance might be seen as a set of nestled black boxes. But the set is not infinite. We reach the "last black box" when we reach quantum limits. If one thinks of causation as equivalent to branching trees of energy exchanges, then at the quantum level there are no more energy exchanges that can form a link between two phenomena.

Yet the phenomena A and B (the cause and the effect) are names given to patterns, or that is to say, signals and signal templates (memories).

But what is a phenomenon? The best answer is to say that it is a signal with key components that remain constant. That is to say, we assume that phenomenon X expresses a thing or event that is replicated or recurs. But in actuality X is normally an approximation and abstraction of many experiences. So empirically one's brain determines that when A occurs, the probability is high that B follows. When the learned probability is very high, we say that "A causes B," forgetting that A and B are as much abstractions as a Euclidean line. This abstraction is real as a limiting or axiomatic form but is not itself replicable, except perhaps as a memory template. (The ideal of a horse is the set of attributes that define what we mean by this phenomenon.)

Even so, mathematics, mathematical logic and hard sciences don't seem altogether empirical. Yet, what we have in science is a system of relations as in "if xRy and yRz, then xRz." So pure math and logic provides a system or systems of abstraction that are used to undergird the relations found by physicists and other scientists. Still, these science relations are based on assumptions about abstractions such as massive object, force and energy which "work" in the sense that they can be used for assigning higher or lower probabilities to "A implies B."

But even if one proves that xSv implies xRy, one can rarely be sure that abstraction x represents a unique information string rather than some unordered set of such strings. If the latter, sometimes some x0 will occur without being paired to any y, forcing us to account for such outliers by incorporating a margin of error.

But our basic point is that cause and effect are in many respects a product of the mind's means of perception and estimation. Whether there are causes and effects in some background frame of reality is not evident.

What is meant by the word abstraction? This is a freighted question, and we will avoid most of the deep philosophical issues, but certainly it is related to the concept of codification, whereby a short data string is used to represent a longer one. Note that if a coding is going on, then there is information in the function that transforms string A into string B, and so abstractions tend to have relatively high information values.

One might also accept that modern naive set theory, or an axiomatic formalism such as Zermelo-Fraenkel, is a good basis for conceptualization. Further -- realizing that much computer math can be represented with matrices or, in general, via group theory -- we can think of a data set embedded in a matrix. For example, suppose we have some well-chosen augmented square matrix AB, where B is a column vector whose elements are all 1's. Then A, through a sequence of row-column transformations, can be uniquely represented as as IA'or simply A'. Now A' condenses the data of A (though the number of bits per column element tends to rise) so that it can be said to uniquely represent A.

The information content increases with each transformation.

We can of course stop anywhere between A and A' and the intermediary matrix CD might be construed to have a lower level of abstraction than A'.

Of course an abstraction, expressing some recurrent pattern, is worthless -- in fact, can't exist -- without memory. The pattern must be stored for potential use later, though patterns left unused may extinguish. We suggest that any perceptual pattern X -- the memory template -- has an emotional value associated with it, which helps prioritize the brain's tasks. In other words, X has a pain (avoidance) value between 0 and some maximum, and likewise for pleasure (attraction). If X has a (0,0) value, then it probably would not be retained in storage.2x Clearly, a pattern's E-value can and does evolve with time, as the bio-system records a value for each new occurrence of X and then uses a weighted averaging method to assign a new value. These two scores are used to prioritize the system's handling of the recognized signal. The overall process is made obvious from the phenomenon of extinction, whereby a desire-based or fear-based behavior gradually extinguishes if no significant association with reward or punishment occurs during recurrences of X. (Of course, there is always the possibility that non-learned -- "hard-wired" -- reactions to specific signals can have a relatively constant E-value over time.)

[Clearly, we have, like others, simply updated Bentham's utility calculus.]

So pattern recognition -- which we shall discuss further later on -- and causality go hand in hand. There are various logico-mathematical systems for encapsulating the idea of causality. It is handy that the matrix multiplication rule for AB = C can be construed as a cause of C. This analogy -- it is perhaps more than an analogy -- reflects the principle of entropy, or, that is to say, the apparent asymmetry of time. The fact that BA need not equal C echoes this asymmetry.

Heisenberg was deeply concerned with the causality issue, though he believed that the mathematics sufficed to give quantum relations and that there was little point in trying to draw a three-dimensional machine that would fit inside a "black box." He certainly had a precedent. Newton's theory of gravitation gave the relations without trying to peek into the cause of "action at a distance." Field theories seem to get rid of that problem, only to disclose equally difficult problems with linear causality.

Various problems in quantum theory, it seems, result from the fact that black boxes are always necessary. For example, the procedure of renormalization is needed to lop off infinities so that calculations are possible. But many are dissatisfied. Still, the method gets results, even if it doesn't "make sense" in accord with standard causality, just as Heisenberg's matrices got results, even though there was no system of levers and pulleys "underneath."

Multiplexing possibilities
We regard the normal human brain as a signal processor that employs a feedback control mechanism.

Before elaborating on the concepts of "signal" and "feedback," let us consider "multiplexing," which is the encoding, transmission and decoding of two or more approximately simultaneous signals.

If we consider a signal as represented by some wave form, then, using, say Fourier analysis, that wave form can be decomposed into lower amplitude components (perhaps harmonics). Now it is unsurprising that two wave forms -- signals -- can superpose. So a scanner tuned to a particular type of wave form of amplitude A will regard that form as the signal and the complement form of amplitude B as noise. Obviously, the scanner's decoding program is critical to determining which signal is received and which is ignored.

In the communications industry, analogue multiplexing may use amplitude or frequency modulation, whereas digital multiplexing is usually done by weaving together messages based on time intervals, knowledge of those intervals being essential for decoding.

Another possibility: Encoder A uses binary numbers from set X intended for Receiver A' and Encoder B uses binary numbers from set Y intended for Receiver B'. X Ã‡ Y may or may not be disjoint. If not, either the intersection is all noise for both parties or Receiver A' may receive a readable, if noisy, message intended for Receiver B' (and possibly the converse as well). Similarly, a multi-node network might yield occasional unintended messages.

We can posit a similar idea for wave analysis. We number the harmonics and assign one set of numbers to harmonics subset X and the other set to harmonics subset Y. If X and Y are not disjoint, then every now and then an unintended but meaningful message may reach a decoder.

An additional consideration: a signal or wave form may be of any finite length (though if long it must be processed piecemeal). We can think of the novel Crime and Punishment as a single signal that could be superposed over Brothers Karamazov, another single signal. If there is a non-empty intersection of the codes of these multiplexed signals, a processor processing these narratives piecemeal could -- in principle -- come up with a fairly readable, if noisy, narrative composed of elements of both stories, though the composite story would likely lack a satisfactory Gestalt.

Though in this example such a an outcome represents an extreme longshot, one can devise scenarios whereby such "readable but noisy" composite narratives are much more likely. Also, we have not yet addressed the feedback control issue in the brain's processing of signals.3x

Feedback control and information
Any organism may be viewed as an entity guided by feedback control. On the other hand it is not obvious what inorganic forms, excepting man-made devices, rate such a descriptive.

A life form may be regarded as a device that works to maintain an information content that is higher than that of the ambient environment. The life form not only has low relative entropy but works, using error correction routines, to maintain the specific information content associated with this low entropy. The information content represents the string of logic gates that works to maintain the circuit, or of the information itself, as with Richard Dawkins' red queen metaphor.

A life form may be seen as a device with the specific "prime directive"4x that it resist the environmental tendency toward entropy increase; that is to say, to maintain a low-entropy volume in a larger volume where entropy increases relentlessly. Because the environment must always win, the only hope of maintaining a high information content is via the copying of the information. As a sophisticated tool for resisting the march of entropy, many organisms have adopted "natural selection" subroutines which permit mixes of information that, over time, tend to preserve the core information content encoded via DNA.5x (Even so, entropy still wins, as the record of species extinction shows.)

Now in order to resist the pressure toward entropy increase, the organism must have a sense of entropy difference. It must monitor the external environment in order to make decisions that decrease the probability that the system represented by the information content will be compromised. Clearly, the organism cannot maintain a state of low entropy without energy going into the error-correcting machinery. To carry out this task, the organism must process a sequence of signals, that require a response or no response. We can think of the organism as a device that monitors a number of parallel-processed signals, some of which may imply a need for conflicting responses.

A negative feedback control system feeds back a small portion of the input in order to influence the behavior of a dynamical system, which means to maintain some constant, or homeostatic, state, which we may call the main goal and which can be represented as information. For example, in cold weather a thermostat measures the internal heat and orders the furnace to fire up or shut down depending on how far from the temperature setting is the measured temperature (the selected temperature is a constant). The thermostat measures a signal in terms of temperature information and regulates its system's state based on the sequence of incoming signals. The thermostat is the brain of the building-furnace system.

Similarly, an organism or coherent colony of organisms, maintains its low entropy state with ensembles of feedback control mechanisms. The constant state is some essential information content that corresponds to the survival imperative. In order to maintain this basic state, the environment is monitored and the information from it sent to the error-correction system. The monitors adjust their activities in accordance with the input signals, which then influences the organism's output (behavior). In other words, the monitors check the results of the output, or behavior, and feed that information back into the error-correction system. (Behaviorshould be taken to mean any activity of the animal, including "idle" periods.)6xa

The environment is represented to the organism as a set of signals, many operating in parallel and some being in superposition. The sentient organism's reality is the signal stream that comes within the purview of consciousness. The need to maintain the basic internal code may extrapolate to a strategy of modifying the external environment up to a short range -- such as by moving toward acceptable heat or fleeing a predator. The organism only samples those types of data from the environment necessary for survival -- even though it may appear that some activity or other is unrelated to the survival imperative -- so that much environmental information is essentially nonexistent.6x

Though a feedback control system is programed to maintain some constant, its subroutines may use variables, which is indeed the case for a sentient being.

Let's consider a maze, which must be got through to obtain some sub-goal. By trial and error, the correct path is mapped into the brain. A wrong result is fed back into the memory so that it won't be used again. But a maze can have numerous paths to the goal. The brain may accept a "good enough" path and decide it not worthwhile to expend energy toward shortening the time. But if time is a major factor, the brain might try all paths and then settle on the shortest (barring any unpleasantries en route).

But what if the maze contains doors at the forks, and these doors sometimes open and close if the animal learns some key? Then the game becomes much more complex, but the feedback principal still is at work.

Goals and behavior
A negative feedback system has one constant state, or goal, that it is designed to maintain. That system may employ a number of secondary feedback systems, the goals of which are elements of the primary goal. The primary goal is hard-wired and some of the secondary goals may also be hard-wired (archetypes in Jungian language), whereas other goals may be formed by the software program. This would be equivalent to finding the best route through a maze to obtain the bit of cheese that the animal has learned is very likely to be had.

We may represent a goal G as a matrix of numbers standing for various signal pulse strengths. In order to satisy a matrix -- reach a goal -- the system may test a number of algorithms, each of which has some probability of success. After a number of trials, the system selects an algorithm with the best (or at least "good enough") success rate. In fact, we may design neural networks such that the system runs various sub-routines and, through repetition, learns probabilities.

The brain's means of learning seems well-represented by conditional probability methods. Consider some primary goal and draw a tree diagram of routes to the result. As the brain runs the system through trials of these paths, it assigns probabilities to each leg which it memorizes (rarely consciously). Again, the optimal path learned is not necessarily objectively the best path. We may have parallel trees for different goals, but these goals are still secondary to the primary goal of pleasure/not pain, which would usually have the highest emotion value of 21/2x1/2, with x very high.2x. In other words fear of death corresponds to fear of the unknown, which carries a high pain template value; desire to live may correspond to numerous remembered pleasant life experiences. Clearly, this emotion value is not uniform, as the suicide rate demonstrates.7x

The feedback occurs in the process of testing to ensure that an optimal path is memorized. In fact, the memory function is an essential part of the feedback loop. Importantly, the feedback control system may continually test paths to see whether the currently accepted optimum still holds. But there are limits on this process as behaviors, choices and social interactions become ever more complex. If internal feedback control worked well at high levels of complexity, the jails would be empty.

Plainly, pathologies ("bugs") occur in software that deploys feedback control systems, as, for example, when self-defeating closed loops form as addictive or repetitive compulsive behaviors. Some pathologies occur when the brain learns that to obtain self-pleasure, it must inflict self-pain -- though the phrases "delayed gratification" and "no pain, no gain" reflect a need to balance fundamental goals.

The tree-diagram representation works for discrete time intervals, whereby each tree diagram's probabilities either remain the same or change by time interval. But the diagrams -- each corresponding to some template memory pattern -- themselves are often continually evolving.

While fear of the unknown has an obvious Darwinian point, delight in the new can also be cast in Darwinian terms. The hunter must discover, must solve problems. Also newness relates -- along with its soulmate, creativity -- to what Freud called libido, whereby creativity is the sublimation of sexual needs. The species prospers through heterosexual variation -- though not too much, as that increases risk of disease. What we are getting at is that there is a powerful mechanism to find or produce new patterns -- but not too new. These patterns need be composed of existing stored patterns, or memory templates, just as two or more wave forms can superpose as a composite signal.

Again, matrices prove useful in representing goal-directed (feedback) systems, where AB very well may not equal BA. Suppose the system has determined that goal A cannot be achieved without sub-goals B and C. It may also have determined that B then A obtains goal C but that the converse doesn't work. (Markov chain matrices may prove of value when modeling such a system.)

Cognition that a goal has been achieved is much the same as recognition of a pattern. In the same vein as Google asking whether you meant "New York City" rather than "New York Sity," a matrix is considered satisfied when there is a good match of template elements with incoming data. This form of error-forgiveness makes sense because the probability of accuracy increases exponentially with each accurate element. Nevertheless, this "good fit" approach is hardly infallible, as when one calls out to a "familiar" person, only to learn that the set of initial clues was associated with a stranger. This method of estimation strongly influences the "construction of reality," as discussed below.

Focus is a particularly important concept. When one thinks of focus, one may think of some sort of conscious process, but we may roughly define focus as the pursuit of some goal, though the goal may be some complex mental construct. Hence focus becomes the mechanism for pursuing and staying with a specific goal. In turn, this is a consequence of prioritization of goals that are either hard-wired or have been programed into the software. So focus then becomes a function of the E-value for a specific goal. An emergent incoming signal (or pattern) may trigger a higher E-value associated with the stored template. The system then shifts focus.

In a human, the so-called "left-brain" pattern recognition, abstraction and manipulation systems are sufficiently robust to yield third- and fourth-generation software programs for obtaining goals, meaning that the composite signal -- made up of the input signals, the feedback loop signals and the output signals -- is, if not chaotic, at least highly unpredictable in many respects.

It seems self-evident that consciousness is differentiated with degees of alertness. So we'd say that a stream of consciousness can be represented as a composite signal of variable amplitude, though an average amplitude can be used for a basic state, corresponding to such activities as reading an instruction manual, or dozing on the train. The amplitude for alertness is closely related to focus.

Thoughts and thought constituents (or "sub-thoughts") would be modeled as wave forms guided by a carrier wave, which varies, in form and amplitude, with the higher alert states and the trance-like or sleeping states.

So we would say that human brain's feedback control system runs both parallel and hierarchical programs for the monitoring of incoming data and output behavior. That output behavior includes the stream of consciousness (though the machine paradigm may not be satisfactory from a philosophical point of view, of course). The output, influenced by a number of variables, has a chaotic tendency, rather like the weather. On the other hand, as with weather forecasting, some underlying behaviors are quite probable, as psychological warfare experts and blackmailers have learned. Some of these sub-systems may be linear, but the overall effect seems to be that these goal-pursuit activities express a non-linear dynamical system.

Moreover, in that survival depends on good estimation of outcomes, the human mind tends to favor linear "cause-effect" interactions. In order to obtain such linearity, it uses probabilities to determine the likelihood of B, given A, even though the patterns A and B are in fact generated within a non-linear system.

Construction of reality
We will give a working definition of reality as "meaningful interaction with a perceived environment." Meaningful is any interaction associated with some emotion value. The emotionless cold logic of Star Trek's Mr. Spock is, we suggest, insufficient for perception and consciousness. The amygdala's valuation of experiences is essential for the prioritization process necessary for human consciousness.8x Even when one applies cold logic to the solution of a particular problem, one does so based on some emotion-based need.

Does this mean that the "objective external environment" is emotionally colored? In a word, yes. Focus is predicated by goals, which have E-values. Of course, the engineer and the scientist wishes to filter out the subjective aspects of "the environment" or problems under study. Essentially, this means that there is an assumption that the intersection of a number of skilled minds leaves a set of relations that are stripped of subjectivity.

No longer is one's mind the creator. The agreed principles of reality are said to precede this.

I have not attempted to answer either the solipsists or the mechanistic representationalists. What is intended is to show that the brain does indeed construct perceived reality.

The term percept is a term generally reserved for sentient lifeforms. It is at the level of percept that the line of distinction between conscious awareness and mechanistic awareness blurs, and I must leave that blur in place. I offer no conjecture as to what constitutes the kernel of consciousness.9x

To approach the percept concept, let us use a heuristic device. Consider a video. Each frame is an element of a longer signal. A percept is analagous to a video frame. There exists some quantum (using the term advisedly) of perception whereby the brain processes a specified set of data (which we might represent with matrices) in some basic time interval.

The percept occurs once a match has been made between an incoming data set and a template pattern. This match generally occurs before it reaches the conscious level. There is a reason for this delay. The percept not only matches a data set against a memorized pattern, it also must "fit" into the stream of awareness, as has been demonstrated with the phi effect.

Hence cognition -- what occurs as a consequence of a percept or set of percepts -- is a composite event. We should regard, at some basic stratum, a number of percepts as being superposed (running in parallel but having a Gestalt effect) to form a focus percept set. Again, focus is dictated by parallel and hierarchical goals, some of which are hard-wired and many of which are evolved from the "software."

Different brain mechanisms are scanning for various high-priority patterns. These patterns usually superpose. These superpositions may be cast in terms of the composition of a matrix with sub-matrices, or as the compisition of a wave form with sub-wave forms, perhaps at the level of harmonics.

So we are talking about a set of percepts represented, say, as a high information (many superpositions) wave form. I do not say that a percept necessarily corresponds to some harmonic. I don't know.

However this may be, we would say that a stream of consciousness may be treated as a signal represented by a composite wave form over some basic interval associated with a percept. As noted earlier, different percepts have typically different durations, and so we would expect a composite percept's duration to either be as long as the longest-time sub-percept or to vary with the longest-time sub-percept.10x So then, we would treat the typical stream of consciousness as a continually but discontinuously changing wave form. The aperiodicity of course does not extend to the essential components, such as biorhythmic "carrier waves" and other elemental wave forms.

On the difference between sense datum and sub-percept

For us, a sub-percept is a minimal matrix such that the human cognitive system uses it as a potential element in decision-making, whether at the autonomic (usually if not always) or conscious level. It goes into the computation chain in the continuing drive toward homeostasis. Someone may notice a sensation. In that case, perception occurs. A group of sense data (those physical inputs that trigger neurons) has been spotted as potentially requiring a decision, such as withdrawing one's feet from proximity to a radiator -- a response that may be consciously perceived or unconsciously so, depending upon the urgency of the need. At the very lowest level, the perception process discriminates among data, throwing most away as useless. So discarded data have been "perceived" by a basic analyzer or analyzers. Those that are retained are inserted into a "matrix" (in mathematical terms), and one or more analyzers at the next stage "decides" on whether action is required or whether to discard. This process may continue through several stages, with negative feedback making the process more complex as we go up the hierarchy.
Yet, on account of other ideas in this paper, we must concede that philosophically our descriptions here bring us to the difficulty of exactly what a supposed physical input really is. But we refrain from attempting to resolve this solipsistic issue.

In this light, we must take into account wave packet dispersion, or delay dispersion. Though not important at the quantum level, delay dispersion is routine in the so-called macro-world. That is to say, a phenomenon signal, composed of numerous subsignals, is likely to be subjected to delay dispersion because some of the subsignals taken from memory are showing entropy's wear and tear. This effect also helps to ensure that the overall reality signal is highly variable and generally aperiodic.

Oliver Sachs has told of a noted musician whose short-term memory was so severely limited by a brain disorder that he lived in a state where from moment to moment he felt as if he had just become conscious, though he could still function to some extent because process-system memories of how to do things -- such as play music or converse -- were still operational, though in a sharply limited sense. The condition of the musician, now deceased, demonstrates that the impression of continuity that an unimpaired person has derives from many stored patterns being brought into play. Moreover, we see that some of the feedback control systems can still run without much input of information via the consciousness. Despite his abilities, however, the musician was subjected to a highly unpleasant discontinuity -- somewhat akin to watching a video with far too many frames missing.

Research into visual perception demonstrates that the brain constructs the three-dimensional view of the world. No logical or philosophical imperative requires that the world "out there" have three spatial dimensions. When one thinks of the word dimension, one may say that dimensions are part of "concrete reality," but in fact they are mathematical abstractions that we moderns use in coping with our ideas about reality. We might easily argue that human perception approximates within some range what happens in some n-dimensional (n greater than 3, or 4, if you include time) manifold. In fact, the melding of the spatial dimensions and the time dimension into a Minkowski-Einstein spacetime continuum underscores this point.

(Interestingly, though Einstein was delighted with the potential of the Kaluza-Klein five-dimensional spacetime frame, he made a serious effort to keep their mathematics but avoid having spacetime be "really" five-dimensional. Einstein's reformulation found little favor.)

These days, string theorists suggest that we can't "see" posited extra dimensions because they are too tiny, being "curled up" at a quantum level. This disability would be analagous to not being able to see the edge of some extremely thin object.

Yet the idea that three space dimensions correspond to some objective "concrete" set of phenomena is, at root, an unproved assumption. This cosmic stuff with which the brain interacts needn't correspond to any visualizable images. In fact, quantum discoveries tend to underscore that point.

The concept of dimension stems from the abstraction of the notion of edges in Euclidean solid geometry and also is, intuitively, related to the up-down sense from gravitational effects. We might add that the brain's method of decoding signals as "moving objects" despite these objects continually changing in apparent size and shape helps to impress on us the intuitive notion of dimension. If we regard a moving object in terms of signaling, we get some idea of how this process works. The brain detects some core pattern and compares it with the relatively static background visual field. The change in the background field is perceived as motion and the incremental changes in the "object" set give rise to the perception of morphological change.

However this may be, most cosmic stuff goes undetected by the unaided brain, and what is detected is registered on a signal processing system used to keep the body and brain in equilibrium (despite disequilibriums, such as illness or wild behaviors that occur as a consequence of systemic complexity).

The brain's determination of depth11x is also part and parcel of our intuitive idea of dimension. The brain uses visual clues to transform two-dimensional surfaces into three-dimensional ones. Donald Hoffman12xhas given a number of interesting examples of these constructions.

And of course depth perception is heavily dependent on wave interference. The two-eyed vision system is a device for measuring such interference (though the vision system is more than this, being highly integrated into the brain's various means of processing data). Standard photographs and paintings do not contain those interferences and so the brain interprets them as flat, even though the brain uses visual clues to give a measure of mock depth. In fact, it is perhaps significant that a hologram is fractal-like in that small portions of the photographic plate replicate the entire image in 3-D, though precision declines with scale. This bolsters our contention that phenomenal reality is constructed from closely packed information.

Bohm's concept of some implicit order that makes bilocalism more determinate fits with the idea that the brain is interacting with some sort of projection. In fact, it is clear that the brain projects some reality. But is it possible that the brain is able to operate analagously to a holographic projector, reading information from some unvisualizable "place" and projecting that information via some sort of wave interference? However that may be, the brain cannot detect a pattern without having a closely matching template pattern for comparison. The incoming data stream must be analyzed -- i.e., broken down into convenient small signals that can be matched against stored signals. But, as we tried to emphasize in the section on multiplexing, there is often more than one way to break down the incoming data and reconstitute it into something readable. As an analogy, one may get a string of letters and be able to decode a sensible English sentence plus some noise and a sensible Swedish sentence plus some noise. The processer must know what it's looking for.

So we see that, in principle, there is no way to distinguish actual reality from virtual reality, a point well known to science fiction writers but not well accepted by most scientists.13x As optical illusions and ambiguous patterns demonstrate, the brain constructs a phenomenon based on stored data. In the case of an ambiguous pattern, the brain can only discern one of the two superposed signals. While focused on the selected signal it is blind to the alternate state (AKA the alternate construction, the alternate phenomenon, the alternate reality). If prompted, it may see the alternate pattern, but as it does so, it becomes blind to the previous pattern. If it views the superposition pattern, then it sees neither sub-pattern while entertaining the collective pattern. Of course, the brain can hop back and forth rapidly for simple constructions but much more complex signals may not be so easily "jumped out of."

Consider the Necker cube. If the figure is presented as completely symmetrical, one usually sees a two-dimensional six-gon divided into six similar triangles. It is possible for some people to see the figure as a cube, but this usually requires a conscious attempt (perhaps organized by the left hemisphere) to do so. A standard Necker cube is however ambiguous (perhaps the right hemisphere's processing is affected), whereby one usually sees a mock three-dimensional cube in one of two possible orientations. When the brain first scans the figure, it detects, prior to consciousness, the superposed states of A and B, which is the flat state. The brain of a modern (habituated to mass media imagery) reads the clues and ordinarily chooses either orientation/state A or orientation/state B, thus collapsing the wave function. The brain cannot see the alternate state until the previous state has been suspended, implying that the brain for a short period temporarily revives the superposition.

The Necker cube demonstrates that the brain constructs reality, though when the data are sparse enough, the reality can be discerned as mock or simply representational. In fact, one way the brain can discern that the phenomenon isn't "real" or "serious" is by switching back and forth between states.

Closely related to this construction process is the notion of Gestalt. When two subsignals superpose and are recognized as meaningful, we call that cognition a Gestalt effect. The Gestalt reaction may be a consequence of hardware or software functions.

In the case of the Necker cube, the Gestalt reaction ordinarily doesn't stem from superposition of states A and B but from the superposition of sub-signals that constitute perception A or perception B.

As we know from internet programs designed to thwart automated access, pattern recognition is not a simple matter. Suppose we have a (say equilateral) triangle and draw two intersecting lines such that one side in linked to two lines and each of the other sides is linked to one line. A spontaneous identification of the numeral 4 is unlikely, but if told that the figure contains a 4, the observer sees it by deconstructing the figure and cognizing the appropriate subsignal while defocusing the remaining signal. Again, we see that meaningful (not mere noise) reality is constructed by the brain either by decomposition of superposed signals or by the combining of signals into a composite signal.

Interestingly, we may say that the figure we've described is composed of two subsignals, but that only holds if there are templates for those sub-signals. The 4 exists because it is a common visual signal used in an important process known as counting. So it is with superposition of more complex phenomenon signals.

Another example: take a collection of five stones each colored differently and arrange them in a circle. How many ways can we arrange this circular pattern? Let us name the colors as B,R,G,P,W and let B be fixed relative to the others. With respect to B, there are 4! (24) patterns. But, in a ring, there is no difference between a permutation and its mirror image, and so the total number of patterns is 4!/2, or 12.

The fact that we get two numbers for the same set of stones, (n-1)! and (n-1)!/2 is another illustration of the brain's imposition of order on its input signals.

An important issue cited by Davies, Hoffman and others is sometimes known as the phi effect, whereby the conscious brain discerns motion that can only have been constructed by a pre-conscious processing method. The phi effect is most obvious from video film, whereby the brain interprets slightly different still images presented sequentially as if the subsignals in the images represent moving objects.

Hoffman relates experiments with four lights set at corners of a square. At one time interval between flashes, if the lights are flashed sequentially, the observer sees four dots traveling in straight lines. At a shorter interval, the observer sees one illuminated dot traveling in a circle.

Interestingly, the lights can be flashed in such a way that straight line motions might head toward one source, but this interpretation is rejected by the brain, which, says Hoffman, prefers "global coherence of motion."

If stick figures of a symmetrical t and a symmetrical x are alternately flashed at a sufficient rate, the observer sees a whirling windmill.

Numerous experiments of this sort -- pioneered by Max Wertheimer in 1912 -- point to the brain's construction of a meaningful signal from input clues.

We also have the remarkable and telling effect of masking, which engineers deconstruction and forgetfulness of a pattern in order to deal with a replacement pattern.

"It is possible to present stimuli to the brain subliminally (unconsciously)," writes neuroscientist Joseph Le Doux14x. "This can be done in a number of ways, but one commonly used is backwards masking. In this procedure, an emotion-arousing visual stimulus is flashed on a screen very briefly (for a few milliseconds) and is then followed immediately by some neutral stimulus that stays on the screen for several seconds. The second stimulus blanks out the first, preventing it from entering conscious awareness (by preventing it from entering working memory), but it does not prevent the first from eliciting an emotional reaction (the stimulus changes the beating of the heart or makes palms sweat). Since the stimulus never reaches awareness (because it is blocked from working memory), the responses must be based on unconscious processing of the meaning of the stimulus rather than on the conscious experience of it. By short-circuiting the stages necessary for the stimulus to reach consciousness, the masking procedure reveals processes that go on outside of consciousness in the human brain."

We see that an unconscious process chooses the phenomenon signal it has a need to focus on. The brain requires some time interval in which it determines whether a signal perceived by the "reptilian brain" is to be incorporated into the conscious narrative.

In About time, Davies writes that the "essence of phi shows up in experiments in a darkened room where two small spot are briefly lit in quick succession, at slightly different locations." The subjects saw not two successively lit dots but a single dot moving back and forth. Usually each dot is illuminated for 150 milliseconds followed by a dark period of 50 milliseconds. "Evidently the brain somehow 'fills in' the 50-millisecond gap. Presumably, this hallucination or embellishment occurs after the event, because until the light flashes, the subject cannot know the light is 'supposed' to move."

In another experiment, the first spot is colored red and the other green, Davies wrote. Subjects reported seeing the dot change color in the middle of the imagined trajectory. So how does the subject experience the correct color before the green spot lights up?

Plainly, a lag time permits the brain to cobble together signals into a consciously perceived signal that "makes sense," in accordance with some Darwinistic imperative.

Davies writes that Daniel Dennett15x argued that the receiver system initially only records the red spot and then the green spot but that an "Orwellian in-built censor" rejects the initial reality and constructs another, causing the observer to forget the initial discrete observations.

We might add that for such basic percept or pre-percept signals, the rules for organizing them into a meaningful signal are highly time-dependent.

We may wonder about the mechanism for distinction between the perception of the self as "behind the eyes" and the remainder of the world as "out there." I don't have a good mechanistic answer as to perception of qualia, or of self.16x

But I would say that the feedback control system is not able to monitor all of its interior elements, analagous to the results of Goedel and Turing that show that a computer cannot compute a proof of every true statement, that its circuitry must be in this sense be incomplete.

Construction of reality occurs not only at basic levels but at all levels (except perhaps at some metaphysical ultimate level). As Eric Kandel17x has noted, much post-behaviorist research verifies Freud's basic point that many conscious perceptions and goals are driven by unconscious goals.

G. William Farthing18x says such "automated" or "unwilled" activity is explained or rationalized by the interpreter system, which formulates a politically correct narrative expressed via conscious cognition. Farthing notes that the interpreter explanations cannot be entirely accurate because it cannot scan all the computational activities of these "nonconscious modules" [whether they be hardware or software programs].

Further, as work with brain-damaged patients shows, the interpreter system is not limited to coming up with convincing, politically correct stories to mask and repress from consciousness the infantile or animalistic hidden agendas, it can also concoct reality streams that explain anomalies linked to the disorder.

Farthing is far from alone when he insists that mental unity is an illusion. "Our actions are not controlled by the executive system. Most of them, including many complex cognitive acts, are products of nonconscious modules." He adds that "our culturally instilled, folk-psychological belief in conscious control of our actions is so strong that when the left hemisphere interprets the behaviors elicited by nonconscious modules, it typically interprets them as if they had been consciously controlled."19x

Steven Strogatz20x tells of a 1999 study in which electrode-linked subjects were shown "Mooney faces," ambiguous black-and-white images that, viewed in one orientation, look like faces, but viewed "upside down," are meaningless blobs. About a quarter second after a subject scrutinized the image, the monitor displayed a number of "gamma oscillations" caused by millions of neurons firing rhythmically at around 40 Hertz in various cortex regions associated with visual processing. These gamma oscillations occurred for subjects reporting a face or a blob at the point when unconscious recognition occurred.

Even so, notes Strogatz, though the firings occurred in each case, the degree of synchrony was radically different. Only when the "rightside up" face was viewed did the electrical discharges align themselves in farflung parts of the brain. Yet, before the subject pushed a button to signify recognition of a familiar type of image, the synchrony dissolved. Again, the brain is constructing a phenomenon signal from the input data, which is why there needs to be a time lag prior to consciousness.

The murkiness of the concept of free will is driven home by V.S. Ramachandran21x, who cites a study in which EEG-wired subjects were instructed to wiggle a finger at any time of their own choosing within a ten-minute period. Researchers found that 0.75 second before a finger wiggled, the EEG recorded a "readiness potential," even though each subject's conscious awareness of a decision to wiggle coincided almost exactly with the actual wiggling.

From the foregoing, it would appear that there is no remedy for the situation whereby one's thoughts contribute strongly to "wave function collapse."

The importance of narrative continuity
Among the earliest modern computing instruments was the World War II anti-aircraft calculator, which predicted the probable position of an aircraft based on the plotted trajectory. Hopefully, artillery shells would intercept the plane at the correct time and place.

In other words, the calculator constructed a probable future trajectory and aimed its guns as if that trajectory would continue, at least for a short time.

It is suggested here that the brain's reality construction program includes a projection of "reality trajectories" that developed as a means of assisting the organism in coping with threats and needs.

As we see from the phi effect examples above, the brain groups several inputs that are spaced at short time intervals into a cohesive whole that is experienced as a now (though the subjective experience of this nowis rather nebulous). But the point is that the consciously perceived reality signal includes parts of the signal that have been supplied by the brain as a probably correct, and this includes a projection into the close future.

In other words, imagine the reality signal represented as an incoming wave form mapped onto a t-y grid. The brain plots the probable continuation of the signal into the close future22x, based on stored patterns. Over this "percept interval," sharp jumps in the curve are disallowed, the processor being programed to find good matches.

But this overall reality signal is composed of many sub-signals -- some smeared to one degree or another by delay distortion -- so that at a particular juncture in the perception stream, one subsignal, prompted by the feedback-regulated focusing mechanism, may gain amplitude at the expense of the others. At times, a subsignal's amplitude falls so rapidly as to be blocked from memory.

Even though the brain can select what "future" to construct, it demands that the reality narrative be smooth and continuous. Suppose that two "percept frames" (speaking a bit loosely here) were disjoint, that the phi effect was suspended. Such a disruption confers no survival advantage on the organism, because it doesn't assist in estimation of threat or potential reward. As studies of brain-damaged patients show, the brain manufactures interpolations to come up with a smooth story convincing to its self.

A simple example: I might wish to express that I had said something incorrectly. So I begin, "I mis..." and at that point am confronted with the choice of "...spoke" or "...stated that point." The choice then determines the remainder of the sentence and could well influence my subsequent line of thought. There is also the possibility of superposition, which is sometimes amusing, as when George Bush combined the possibilities "misunderstood" and "misestimated" into "misunderestimated." (We might regard a pun as a superposition of usually two ideas that carry an unexpected Gestalt, or meaning associated with the superposition, but of course it is difficult to plumb the depth of the word idea.)

Occasionally two phenomenon signals might cancel completely for a substantial period. It's also possible that the overall reality signal of a conscious person nearly cancels, possibly being experienced as some Zen-like, meditative state or as free-floating anxiety. Yet a normal alertness amplitude and the E-magnitude would mean, I presume, that some sense of experiential awareness is happening.

What if I were sitting here in the library typing busily and suddenly my laptop word processor vanishes from beneath my fingers? My brain would likely find such a disjunction unacceptable and even manufacture a plausible explanation for how it went missing. Maybe I "remember" going to the restroom and returning to find the machine gone. Such narrative interpolation and "false" memory constitute a well-known effect among the brain-injured. My brain, I suggest, would cope with such a disjunction as if it had been stricken with a brain injury.

So, granting that there is some raw data stream sampled by the brain, the brain recognizes patterns in this stream and strings them together according to some probabilistic method.

Philosophically, we draw close to the many worlds interpretation in that, ordinarily, once a narrative-chain is set off, it has a "logic of its own." That is to say, we may consider it for the most part self-determining (the feedback control system is the story editor). Hence, once a reality subsignal gains sufficient amplitude, it strongly influences the way the story goes. At certain points, the probability of subsignal A gaining sufficient amplitude versus subsignal B gaining that amplitude may be close to 0.5, so that some effectively random influence determines which branch the story will take.

So perhaps we can appreciate the possibility of a many worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics in terms of virtual reality, whereby a reality signal is very convincing to the subject, but is only one of a number of possible decodings and construction-projections.

Interestingly, Deutsch's many worlds variant has parallel universes weakly interfering, as if the branch universes are signals and the set of universes a large composite signal.

Still, when someone you know dies, that's awfully real, even if, notionally, they might be alive elsewhere. Once the brain is on a particular storyline, it finds it difficult if not impossible to escape that virtual reality. The brain's story editor plays the role of the cherubim guarding the gates of Eden, preventing a limitless reality.

In fact, there may be a reason for certain traditions concerning the malleability of reality. Modern man has learned on more than one occasion that "silly ideas" of long ago may usually be as absurd as they seem, but not always. Much modern pharmacology, for example, is based on primitive herbal remedies.

A few common aphorisms concerning the malleability of reality:

1. Life is but a dream.
2. As a man thinketh, so is he.
3. You reap what you sow also known as the law of karma.
4. Faith that moves mountains.
5. Believe without a doubt and what you seek will occur.

In this scenario, intensity of belief affects reality construction.

Obviously, our model is lacking many things and unable to explain many points. For example, we have not addressed the issue of whether such a feedback system implies a need for a higher power, or higher mentality, to keep the "game" going.

Let us distinguish three types of signal superposition:

1. The receiver decodes the interference. When signal A and signal B interfere, we have A intersection B, meaning "x element of A and x element of B."

2. The receiver does not read the composite signal, but only a component signal. In other words, we have A junction B, meaning "x element of A xor x element of B."

3. A third type is a composition of 1 and 2, as in "A junction B xor A junction C." This may apply to the case of individual photons detected randomly, but within constraints that statistically yield an interference pattern.

It is to be expected that the brain would usually use Type 3 decoding, whereby the composite signal is built up from Type 2 signals. Nevertheless, just as wave mechanics in general disregards individual photons and uses Type 1 decoding, so would much brain processing fall under Type 1 decoding. Yet just as Type 2 decoding is necessary for certain aspects of quantum mechanics, so may Type 2 decoding be useful in accounting for a higher degree of reality malleability than is usually accepted.

In his book Noise (Viking Penguin 2006), Bart Kosco, an electrical engineering professor, says that you could tell if your brain were a computer chip or if you were trapped in a Matrix-like virtual reality by the aliasing effect, a term that describes the mind's perception of wagon wheel spokes going backward in old films. Aliasing occurs because the spokes are rotating faster than the film speed. Yet Kosco is implicity positing a passive observer of a film-strip type of reality. But our model requires extensive feedbacks, which might well remove aliasing effects. Even so, pseudo-aliasing effects occur with strange coincidences.

If perceived reality is highly malleable, then we could posit a scenario in which the story signal projects a recurrent subsignal within a relatively short time period. Though there may be more than one mechanism for such an eventuality, it appears that focus, bolstered by some E-value, could yield a burst of highly similar subsignals in the larger reality signal. When these similar subsignals are close in amplitude, the perceiver may notice the coincidences.

In fact, I suggest that "strange coincidences" are part of the case for phenomenal reality being far more dreamlike than ordinarily accepted. What Jung calls synchronicity, whereby some similar incidents intuitively transcend mechanistic randomness (recognizing that intuition is often wrong), would be partly explainable in terms of wave interference, signal decoding and reality projection. The "strange coincidences" would result from an interval of near-coherence of a subset of signals.

Ordinarily, such recurrences are blocked or muted by the fact that the reality wave form, though entrained by the bio-system's overarching needs and system of strongly reinforced memory templates, is far too complex to permit periodicities, which is why we think such bursts of periodicity are strange.

It is remarkable that quantum theory requires that in many situations, such as the two-slit experiment, distinct detections not be exact but be made into a cohesive whole according to some projected pattern (the interference pattern). Similarly, the brain composes cohesive wholes from samples of data that vary with some standard deviation.

Of course we have a circularity issue here. Does quantum mechanics imply reality superposition or does the brain's reality superposition imply quantum results? My answer is that they strictly imply each other and that more work needs to be done to reduce, insofar as possible, the brain/quantum-universe system, to workable elements.

Dreams and altered states of consciousness
Sigmund Freud's Interpretation of Dreams gives the mechanisms of repression, censorship, disguise and conflation. For Freud, conflicting primal goals and emotion-laden life experiences are thrashed out in symbolic form in order to help the brain attain some sort of equilibrium, though in pathological cases the equilibrium is not well attained.41

But why dream? Dreaming requires a type of consciousness that largely leaves out left-brain activity and permits associations of symbols based on primitive similarities. The stream of consciousness is not nearly so smooth, and it is quite possible a laptop might vanish from beneath one's fingers. A typical dream seems to reflect an infantile or animalistic consciousness -- the way a baby actually interacts with the world.

In fact a dream, like an internal fantasy or novel or Hollywood movie, often seems to fill a need for vicarious reality. But why does a person need a vicarious experience? It may stem from early man's need to show others where the game was spotted. This vicarious reality is essential to human speech, which mimics, to a limited degree the brain's feedback controlled reality construction system.

Also, I suggest that the right brain, when representing its goals and conflicts in a dream, is actually attempting to formulate a reality scenario that meets its standards but lacks the left-brain's ability to make narratives smooth and continuous, and so the dreams simply stop abruptly. Such a dream state is in many ways similar to an alcohol-induced blackout, whereby the left-brain (including, if you like, the super-ego), is suppressed and the ego is permitted to live riotously without supervision or restraint. Inability to remember what occurred in a blackout is akin to the common inability to remember a dream. Some alcoholics drink just a little before blacking out and then consuming prodigous quantities of intoxicants. This permits the Dr. Jekyll of the ego to be unsupervised by the Mr. Hyde of the superego -- even after the fact.

So though a typical dream, from our perspective, doesn't seem to cause the observer to interact with the external world, we see that a person may be in a dream-like state and interact with the external world, as we also know from other altered states of consciousness.

Except for very high E-magnitude dreams, forgetfulness of a dream and its details is a function of alertness. Interestingly, I have found that if I a wake up quickly and forget a dream, I can sometimes recover the dream if I allow myself to soon return to a trance-like, semi-conscious (right-brain dominated) state. The reason for the amnesia seems to be that the brain doesn't want one reality stream to conflict with the other; the organism wants no confusion occasioned by blending of reality streams.

Of course, we have various levels of dream consciousness. My own experiences suggest a near-blackout level -- partly because the symbols fly so fast and are so disjoint and partial -- that seems to result from illness or physical problems, to mid-level awareness dreams that often occur sequentially and seem to be acting out the same conflict, but with different symbols, to high-awareness dreams close to the conscious state. Usually, the self is simply a passive observer or passive participant, but if I am close to waking up I may assert control and start directing the dream to some extent, as with a fantasy. I am also able to fall asleep (lose left-brain consciousness) by fantasizing, so that my "consciously controlled" fantasy merges into a dream without the left-brain self in charge.

I well recall drifting into a state of semi-consciousness on a long-haul bus and listening to a symphony orchestra play a very interesting, creative piece. My brain was transforming the input of the engine noise into something pleasant. I also found that I could regulate this symphony to a limited degree with a left-brain "conductor" -- as long as the "conductor" wasn't too alert, in which case I would be cognizant of the engine noise.

Pavlov argued that trances corresponded to gradations between the fully alert awake state and sleep. We would add that in some trances the left-brain reality constructor is limited while the right-brain reality constructor rules. Still, full conscious awareness is limited, because left-brain cohesion routines tend to extend conscious awareness. Such effects are routine when drifting off to sleep or listening to music. In some subjects, such a state can be induced by a hypnotist. Notice that a skilled hypnotist can manipulate a subject's mind so that it creates an alternate reality and storyline. The hypnotist's voice perhaps is perceived by the subject's mind, now in an infantile state, as that of a parent.

The sleep-walker is mainly in a dream state but interacts with the "external world" sufficiently to demonstrate the mind's ability to construct its reality.

Similarly, psychotic episodes show that the brain constructs reality, rather than merely observing it. The brain begins to misinterpret data sets in such a way as to bring about dysfunction. Yet one must acknowledge that there are borderline cases in which one man's paranoia is another man's reality. Conspiracies do exist.25x

What of the world view accepted by a typical American? It is actually a wild distortion of "reality." Propagandists and psychological warfare experts operating through a limited media ensure this situation.

The old saw about genius being akin to madness carries a kernel of truth. The creatively inclined individual draws heavily from the right-brain "lateral" connectivity programs (simple associations as opposed to heirarchical associations) in order to obtain new ideas (superpositions) for projects, while using the left-brain functions to meta-organize the project. This unusual dependence on the right brain corresponds with the right brain dominance of some cognitively disordered mentally ill persons.

Intoxicants are a well-known source of reality distortion. A drug such as LSD, through causing excessive firing of neurons, may yield visual and auditory hallucinations or may stimulate a revision of the belief system incorporated by the individual, with potentially dangerous consequences. Again, we see that the brain concocts reality from raw input data.

In the case of "cold turkey" withdrawal from alcohol or opiates, the subject experiences vivid hallucinations, often in the form of monsters or voices urging suicide. The goal of satisfaction of the addictive need is so great as to strongly affect the functioning of the reality construction mechanism. The organism's desire for suicide stems from its need to end the crisis associated with its lack.

The sleep-deprived often see phantoms, such as a road-sign looking like a waving person in the way. During sleep the brain organizes the day's principle perception sets. In fact, dreaming may be part of that organization process. However that may be, energy is required to maintain a highly-organized left-brain controlled reality narrative. When energy levels are low, that mechanism works poorly.

Very significantly, those deprived of sensory stimulation for days on end begin to construct reality narratives in which minor external stimuli play a major role. The small stimulus is amplified with a set of memory templates. In other words, lucid dreaming results. The brain must "live life." Even low levels of boredom are, from a Darwinist standpoint, counterproductive. The organism needs a rich variety of experience, within smooth constraints; such variety tends to increase chances for individual survival and group survival via hunting, searching and procreativity.

Also, nearly every human needs interaction with other humans. The need for positive approval is a stalwart of the "herd instinct." (We have not discussed the qualitative notion of love. Though love is very important, we would use an E-value, or set of E-values, associated with a specific object or person, as sufficient for our limited purposes.)

[We will have more to say on Freudian-style group dynamics versus Jung's collective unconscious idea in the section on Jung and synchronicity below.]

A prisoner may be held incommunicado in order to pressure him to cooperate with an interrogator. Relief from boredom and the need for human contact may boost the value of the interrogation session, the captors hope. But such a captive is very likely to enter a dream world and, his grasp of reality weakened, is at a disadvantage in defending himself from telling interrogators what they want to hear, even if it is objectively false. In fact, communist "brainwashing" of American war prisoners -- today called "enhanced interrogation" -- was intended to weaken the brain's reality formulator, thus making prisoners compliant and easily guarded by a few soldiers and more amenable to confessions of doubtful veracity.

Occasionally, the brain's reality constructor may show "minor" disjunctions.

Consider the "case of the missing sock."

When one places loose pairs of socks in a washer and dryer, the brain anticipates that there will be chaotic, or effectively random, mixing and tumbling. At any point, there is uncertainty as to the existence of not only one sock, but the pair. There is a waveform for the pair which is a superposition of the individuals. When this waveform vanishes, there is "no guarantee" that a waveform for an individual will emerge, especially in that socks have low priority and there is no strong belief (the focus amplitude is low) that a particular individual will "be there" later. In other words, the reality formulator may tend to lose a sock in the mixing process.

Yes, statistical arguments can be used to counter this suggested scenario, but our model questions some of the assumptions of modern probability theory, as discussed later.

The vanishing laptop example might seem extreme. But what of the time you casually put down a cup of coffee in a cluttered room with no one else present, turned to do something and then turned to get the coffee, only to find the cup was nowhere in sight? Have you never had such an experience?

Perhaps you searched diligently and then found it in some unexpected place, wondering, "How in the world did I manage that?" but then shrugged off the little mystery. Possibly you searched the entire room diligently but didn't find it. Either you accept that something spooky has happened or you believe you have forgotten leaving the room with the cup in hand.

We suggest that sometimes routine psychological errors run a bit deeper, into the reality formulation area. The change of focus may mask a particular anticipated signal; perhaps when you changed focus you caused a glitch in the signal decomposition procedure. When you turn back, the cup signal isn't decoded; its "wave function hasn't collapsed."

On occasion, such an inexplicable event (or non-event, really) might be related to how your mind is interacting with someone else's, even if you don't "see" them in your "materialist" virtual reality state.

Group reality construction
We can see group minds at work on the internet, perhaps using network theory to give a partial description. The evolution of civilization and its group mind, with its many sub group minds, is like the evolution of an organism continually changing -- sometimes regressively, as in the Dark Ages -- and replenishing itself.

We see from political and economic life that this mind is indeed unconscious (though elites try to manipulate and control it) -- which is to say, irrational. This description, perhaps based in Freudian group dynamics, accepts a conventional mechanistic worldview, with all inter-mind activity mediated by the senses.

From a Jungian perspective, however, the stated existence of paranormal phenomena implies a connectivity that bypasses the ordinary sensory system.

The model we have been urging suggests that the sensory system is not part of a simple decoder, but is also part of the individual reality formulator. How does an individual's reality formulator interact with those of his or her fellows, or that is to say, if an individual dreams his own dream during awake life, how would this comport with the dream-construction of his fellows?

Consider the multiplexing examples above. Different-language messages can intersect and potentially yield meaningful, if noisy, combination messages. Also, a translator program can link two worldviews that are disjoint in many respects but share enough in common so that a "good-enough" function exists between the two.

Consider an English speaker carrying on a radio conversation with a German-speaker through an interpreter; if the interpreter is relatively fast, neither the English speaker nor the German speaker need know that the entire conversation isn't being conducted in one language; neither need know he is speaking to a foreigner. Similarly, a person living in "virtual world A" might interact with someone in "virtual world B" with each unaware of the other's world.

To use a silly example, perhaps Lancelot in King Arthur's court is wooing Guinevere, without realizing Guinevere is Britney Spears who is having boyfriend issues. Britney has no clue that Lance is in another realm altogether.

Yes, we commonly say of someone that "he's in another world." The point here is the extent of that possibility.

But because of the feedback system of each mind/node, our model then implies communal virtual reality. This communal reality is continually changing, much like weather and climate systems. Such a communal reality can be viewed as the intersection of individual reality streams. But this group reality needn't be and probably isn't the background reality of the cosmos. This group reality would correspond more to Jung's notion of a collective unconscious, but in no way disputes the Freudian notion of the group mind. The Freudian group mind tends to be elemental and, in totality, irrational and subject to manipulation of experts in crowd psychology, but it is said to operate via the usual senses. The Jungian collective unconscious is a linkage of minds on some non-material plane that contains ancient knowledge.

(I would never consider myself a Jungian, but I think it important to place my model within a historical perspective. Jung's method is, like Freud's, introspective, subjective and very difficult to verify, and so I take his views (and Freud's) with several large grains of salt -- which is not to say that Jung provides no valuable insights. I think he does.)

I have had numerous personal experiences that suggest some sort of covert linkage among minds, but I won't dwell on them, except to point out that very occasionally I will have a dream in which I wake up thinking that one of the dream people actually represents someone else's mind. I believe this because the qualitative feel of the emotions of the dream figure "aren't mine," but are I suspect those of someone known to me. That mind is invariably in Freudian disguise. Yes, I am aware that one often doesn't apprehend one's own unconscious feelings; yet I believe that I am fairly familiar with their routine qualia. When those qualia differ substantially from those with which I am familiar, then I suspect that the signal hasn't been generated entirely internally.

To me, this accords with the idea that each brain influences the signal processing of the other in ways that transcend and indeed bypass the sensory systems.

Such "back-channel" communication is often ascribed to the spirit world, whereby a dreamer may interact with a spirit other than his own. But then of course we are left with the problem of defining spirit. The assumption is that such entities are non-material and can neither be confirmed nor denied and are hence of no relevance to science.

I am not about to define spirit any more than I am ready to define consciousness. Even so, I would say that the assumption that non-material links are impossible is directly contradicted by relativity theory and quantum mechanics.

Deja vu is sometimes ascribed to this supposed spirit realm. Recent research shows that the deja vu perception can be induced . A pattern is flashed so briefly that a subject grasps it only unconsciously. When the pattern is shown at a longer interval, the subject often has a feeling of having seen it before but can't pin down the memory.

We would say that on occasion a reality stream signal contains a superposition of two relatively complex subsignals. The superposition has its own Gestalt. But so does one of the subsignals; still, the larger pattern blocks from conscious perception the subsidiary pattern.

But non-routine deja vu might occur if a person has somehow changed virtual worlds. The former virtual world is blocked from working memory, but a part of the brain recognizes it.

We would say that closely related to the deja vu experience is meaningful coincidence, whether serial or simultaneous. What we have is several subsignals that interfere at time A that go to constitute part of the overall reality signal at time B. This always happens. But sometimes the subsignals cohere sufficiently so that at the "collapse of the wave function" at time B, they form "meaningful" pairs or sets. The observer sees one or more "echoes" of time A events at one or more future times, though my experience is that these future times tend to be within 24 hours.

Following Von Neumann, we say that the wave function collapses only upon observation by a conscious mind, though the degree and type of consciousness may vary sufficiently so that wave functions don't decompose very predictably.

To use a relevant analogy, consider a simple taut string fixed between two walls. Pluck the string at end A and a moment later at end B and two traveling wave forms are set off. These wave forms are discrete until they pass through each other. Once they are fully superposed the brain cannot discern directly either wave form. It must wait until the waves have continued on before they can be viewed as individuals. So it is with reality subsignals. Yet because the reality subsignals are often very rich, they can be decomposed in numerous ways.

The notion of a cultural mind that "creates" reality goes back to Schelling and his admirers in the Romantic school. Schelling is said to have cautiously identified this collective creator with God. [zz1]. We acknowledge the similarity with our posited reality construction scheme, but here we make no hypothesis about higher intelligent powers. Yet, in contrast to the Romantics, we do assert with Kant that it holds de facto that the world of phenomena requires some noumenal existence, in which the "thing-in-itself" is indiscernible.

Randomness, probability and coincidence
Randomness is a description of information. When do we consider an event or observation to be random?

In a classical sense, we can model an event with a set of force vectors. Some events have fairly large sets of force vectors, many of which have low magnitude. The vector sum -- the cumulative vector -- predicts the next state of the observation.

Even so, quite a few of these low-magnitude vectors can't be observed. We can say that empirically we have learned that the very small vectors tend to cancel out. In some cases, a small vector represents a "tipping point" that changes the vector sum in a drastic way. For example, during the toss of a fair coin, some small vector determines whether the coin lands heads or tails. Over many trials, these small vectors tend to cancel, yielding the "law of large numbers."

So here the concept of random is related to our knowledge of small forces. We can't sum those forces exactly for one event, but we can assess that the small forces vary so little that there is no way to be certain what the next outcome will be.

Essentially then, an outlier event is either the result of a measurement error or the result of a set of small forces becoming coherent, thus amplifying their effect rather than canceling or reducing their effect.

At the quantum level, the probability amplitude is what we can know about the "collapse of the wave function." We cannot predict exactly where the collapse will occur and a particle's impact will be recorded. There seem to be no hidden physical forces that are influencing the outcome. Within constraints, the outcome is non-deterministically or acausally random. I strongly suspect that the collapse is a result of how the brain processes data at a very basic level.

It seems plausible that if the focusing unit is neutral about outcomes, the results are deterministically random, the determinants being within the unit's reality builder software. But this is an insufficient explanation, and in fact, I agree with Penrose that progress in physics, physiology and psychology requires extensive research into this interface.

The word coincidence is taken from Euclidean geometry, whereby two line segments intersect over some finite interval. More generally, we deem two events as coincidental if they have something in common, if they intersect. If the number of elements of the intersection is "high," we may say the coincidence is non-random, but is causally related, perhaps reasoning that the information content of the intersection is so high as to represent error-correction activity. Still, because many small forces can occasionally cohere into a large vector, rather than canceling out, we are unsure whether this coincidence has a causal relation or whether it represents an outlier. Hence the need to run a number of trials.

So the coincident events of a boy meeting a girl he knows at the supermarket may be a result of various unmeasured forces and be held as essentially random, even though the girl suspects not. But, if these types of meetings occur repeatedly over a short duration, the girl will almost certainly be correct to assume he is interested in her.

Also, often "meaningful coincidences" are to be expected without there being any macro-connecting cause or force. Such coincidences are counterintuitive to many people and so they believe that some large mystery force is at work. The birthday problem is a good example of this. If you enter a classroom of more than 23 people whose birthdays are unknown to you, the chance is better than 50 percent that someone shares your birthday. That probability climbs rapidly with number. Another example is the "hidden hand" of a free market not controlled by cartels. There is no central organizing force, but we get the impression one exists because micro-actions can and often do cohere into a "net force vector."

Or consider this scenario: You have two well-shuffled decks of 52 cards; what is your chance that two cards drawn from each deck will match? If we do this "without replacement," we must throw the discards back in and reshuffle after each deal. The probability of a match for any one deal is 1/52 and the complement probability of failure is (1 - 1/52). The probability of 52 failures in a row is (1 - 1/52)52, or about 36%. So this "meaningful coincidence" is not really particularly meaningful.
This example is instructive because this process accounts for quite a few such "strange" coincidences.
In a light-hearted vein, Edward B. Burger and Michael Starbird26x dismiss the idea that a "cosmic conspiracy" might account for similarities such as theses:
     Lincoln and Kennedy were both shot to death

     Lincoln was elected to Congress in 1846
     Kennedy was elected to Congress in 1946
     
     Lincoln was elected president in 1860
     Kennedy was elected president in 1960

     Lincoln's secretary was named Kennedy
     Kennedy's secretary was named Lincoln

     Andrew Johnson, who succeeded Lincoln, was born
     in 1808
     Lyndon Johnson, who succeeded Kennedy, was born
     in 1908

     John Wilkes Booth was born in 1839
     Lee Harvey Oswald was born in 1939
Burger and Starbird argue that "Lincoln and Kennedy were not average citizens. The pile of minutiae through which to forage is truly immense." And so "how likely is it that there are no coincidences of dates and names in any of this blizzard of possibilities?" Their answer: "Essentially zero."

John Allen Paulos has argued similarly about various coincidences concerning 9/11, in particular concerning the numerals themselves (Google his home page for a link to that article).

P.T. Barnum was preoccuppied with the number 13, which he held to be unlucky27x. The superstition associated with the number doubtless influenced his suspicion of it, which was reinforced after two fires. The first destroyed his American Museum on July 13 and the second his Barnum Museum on Nov. 13.

From the perspective of routine probability theory, these coincidental events do not portend a mysterious connection. The probability of two consecutive fires can't be estimated; no doubt many combustibles were kept within and the many visitors would have drastically increased the chance of accidental combustion. The probability of "the same" event occurring on the 13th is (1/30)2, which is low, but a significance analysis would show nothing unsurprising.

Of course there are various ways to estimate the likelihood of randomness. But even if the probability were very low, because there are only two events, one cannot rule out a fluke outlier.

One way to address "remarkable chunks of order" is with Ramsey theory, an area of discrete mathematics aimed at finding what conditions are necessary for a minimum amount of order to appear. The simplest example is the pigeonhole principle. If there are m pigeonholes and n > m letters, then at least one pigeonhole contains at least two letters. If m is much smaller than n, two or more letters share one slot only infrequently, and so we might be struck by the "remarkable coincidence" of the association of these two letters. Elaborations on this concept occur in network theory, and it has been proved that for minimum numbers of links and nodes subregions must have higher information content than the average for network subregions.

The pigeonhole example shows how important the question is in standard probability analysis. Suppose you walk into a large room with a bank of 1,000 pigeonholes, having been told that the rule is that each slot must have at least one letter. Now you walk along and behold! there is a slot with two letters and you see no other slot that contains a pair. You may say what are the chances of such a pair? But as long as there are at least 1,001 letters, there is a 100 percent probability of such a pair existing, though that pair's slot would hold (assuming equivalent average content), double the information of a typical slot. Now if you were standing outside the room, your chance of guessing the number of the slot with the high information is then 10-3.

A discussion of randomness shouldn't ignore the issue of deterministic constraints on predictability. We may have an algorithm whose final outcome cannot be computed, as far as is known, by some shortcut method. The work of predicting the nth value rises with n. The work for computationally difficult problems rises exponentially, versus polynomially for many other problems.

We can say that as n rises, the noise rises with it, so that after some m steps, the noise equals or exceeds the signal. In that case, the nth value is effectively random, within whatever constraints there are.

Completely chaotic systems likewise are effectively random within specified ranges. Periodicity vanishes, and yet periodicity is the key to nearly all forms of prediction. Yet, in the march toward chaos, sometimes there are transient intervals of near-periodicity. These islands of near-periodicity might, depending on the circumstances, look like strange coincidences but in fact are imperceptibly diverging from periodicity until chaos is attained.

Systems "far from equilibrium" may yield counterintuitive effects, as when transient periods of order disrupt the general trend of increasing entropy, as discussed by such researchers as Prigogine, Kaufmann and Strogatz27xa. Sometimes such "spontaneous order" is cast in terms of wave entrainment, whereby a high-amplitude wave form sometimes tends to bring low-amplitude wave forms into phase, or at least into near phase.

As Wolfram and others have noticed, algorithms with a few simple rules may, occasionally, yield high information results, though most rule sets yield low-information results.

Arthur Koestler's Roots of Coincidence31x uses probability arguments in order to help the general reader make sense of J.B. Rhine's work. Even so, Koestler fails to note that Paul Kammerer's alleged "law of seriality" (occurrence of strikingly similar events) must take into account that randomness implies clustering.

For example, consider a sequence of 16 tosses of a fair coin. If the alternating pattern HTHT... occurs, a runs test of randomness gives a normal curve z score equivalent to less than 1 percent. In other words, we would not be confident of randomness. So then, in a run of n >= 16 tosses, the probability of clustering (several heads or tails consecutively) is greater than 99%.

Even so, it is possible to detect apparent non-random clustering. Consider a fair coin tossed 20 times. The probability of 12 heads and 8 tails is 20C8(0.520), which is about 12%. We would not feel terribly confident in ruling out randomness. Yet the probability of obtaining 12 heads and 8 tails in the order 2 tails followed by 10 heads followed by 6 tails, when assessed by a runs test, gives a normal curve z score of 3.49, which is equivalent to a probability of non-random influence of 99.98%.

So, when struck by the seeming unusualness of event coincidence, one must take into account that there are various "non-paranormal" explanations that can be used.

And it must be admitted that much writing on supposedly significant coincidences is intended for the Fate magazine set28x, lacks intellectual value and unfortunately tends to undermine the work of serious inquirers into paranormal phenomena, such as nobelist Brian Josephson.

The probabilistic framework adopted by many scientists rests on some important assumptions:

1. There is no non-material medium for transmission of information other than the "spacetime continuum," whatever that is. Still, that position is challenged by the fact of quantum entanglement and bilocality.

2. There is a "large" percentage of observed reality that is not a mere interpretation or projection of the brain. In other words, the individual is one of many event makers and does not influence or control most observed events. Yet, the example of the Schroedinger cat paradox challenges this assumption.

3. The moon "is there" when one isn't looking. The fact that there seems to be agreement among minds as to the moon's probable "thereness" does not preclude the possibility that it is some sort of projection. The claim that the moon is there when one isn't looking is, at root, a theological matter.

So a "strong virtual reality" view of perception would mean that calculation of probabilities is an acceptable way to estimate outcomes, but that beyond this is the occurrence of "upper hierarchy" subsignals that recur within some interval. Barnum's predisposition to worry about the number 13 could have influenced future events in his life. Of course, there is always the possibility of Freudian-style unconscious sabotage whereby one "accidentally" knocks over a lamp twice running. But we are talking about something more, the mind having a strong influence on the "fabric of reality."

Jung, Koestler and synchronicity
A number of physicists have toyed with the notion that mystical, or even, paranormal phenomena are related to quantum weirdness. Non-physicists Carl Jung and Arthur Koestler are two writers who have pondered this idea in their discussions of synchronicity, which Jung defined as the conjunction of "meaningful, acausal coincidences."

Of course these writers, lacking a mathematical orientation, are dismissed by the bulk of scientists. "Flapdoodle," said Nobelist Murray Gell-Mann of Koestlerian ideas (though later in his book The Quark and the Jaguar he mentions the notion of "goblin worlds."29x Gell-mann was the motive force behind the Santa Fe Institute, whose mission was to provide scientific alternatives to arguments for "intelligent design."

John G. Taylor30x, a mathematician with a background in quantum mechanics, had this to say: "Arthur Koestler argued in his book The Roots of Coincidence31x that, because quantum mechanics seems to have these bizarre features associated with the Einstein-Rosen-Podolsky experiment and the Schroedinger cat paradox, that therefore other bizarre phenomena can also occur in the world. This is, I think, a very dangerous, specious argument."

John Archibald Wheeler recounted that in 1979 he strongly objected to sharing an American Association for the Advancement of Science podium with several parapsychologists, characterizing that field as pseudoscience3a.

While true that neither Jung nor Koestler had a specific idea of how such an interface might occur, they did have the statements of people like Wolfgang Pauli and Pascual Jordan they could cite in their favor.

We must accept however that Koestler, wrote like the skilled journalist and thoughtful person he was but could not be said to have presented a serious scientific case for synchronicity or so-called paranormal pheonomena, other than by recapitulating some of the results of J.B. Rhine. Essentially, his point was indeed that if quantum weirdness operates in the world, then why shouldn't paranormal weirdness also occur? His ideas about "holons" (biological parts roughly equivalent to semi-autonomous states in a federal system) seem to reflect some of Lynn Margolis' thinking on symbiosis versus competition; such activity, Koestler thought, might account for extra- or quasi-sensory perception.

More recently, physicist F. David Peat31xa has argued in favor of a quantum explanation of synchronicity. In fact, a number of the ideas in this paper were stimulated by Peat.

Jung developed his synchronicity idea beyond "meaningful coincidences" to include paranormal phenomena in general. He argued that such peculiarities cannot be dismissed as simple subjective mental aberrations, but require a non-Euclidean spacetime continuum, pointing out that Jordan, a founder of quantum mechanics, had advocated the "idea of relativistic space to explain telepathic phenomena."32x

In 1930, Jung wrote that perhaps time, far from being an abstraction, was a "concrete continuum" that helps account for "acausal parallelism, such as we find, for instance, in the simultaneous occurrence of identical thoughts, symbols and psychic states."33x A Jung biographer, Ronald Hayman, writes that Pauli, who for a time was Jung's patient, had originally come up with the idea, though he did not use the word synchronicity34x. In 1951, Jung and Pauli published jointly two separate papers on synchronicity.36xa 36xb [See first item in Appendix A for an interesting account of the "Pauli effect."]

Koestler wrote that a number of eminent physicists had shown interest in psychic phenomena. An early member of the British Society for Psychical was Joseph J. Thompson, discoverer of the electron, said Koestler.35x A middle-aged Werner Heisenberg subscribed to a multi-layered view of reality as propounded by Goethe, writes Heisenberg's biographer, David Cassidy.37x The nine layers of reality --accidental, mechanical, physical, chemical, organic, psychic, ethical, religious and "genial" -- are rungs on a ladder that shift from the objective to the subjective. While placing quantum physics just below the organic level in the realm of the chemical, Heisenberg believed that in order to comprehend the "grand connections" one must climb the ladder of realities.

Heisenberg, wrote Cassidy, believed that the war reflected "movements in the foundations of human thought" -- a shifting of the layers of reality over the heads of individuals in such a way that "dark demons" loosed on the world took on a greater role than in the past. He saw Nazism and Bolshevism as a "strange sort" of "worldly religion."

A typical scientist might well respond that this sort of speculation demonstrates that philosophy is best left to philosophers, and yet we are left with the impression that still another important physicist senses a connection between quantum issues and so-called occult phenomena.

When discussing "meaningful coincidences," we should take care to distinguish between Freudian-style free-association coincidences and the synchronicity postulate of Jung. For example, in The Psychopathology of Everyday Life Freud observes that a young man's forgetfulness of a phrase reflected an unsconscious conflict concerning a girlfriend who had missed her period. This conflict surfaced in a string of thoughts expressed during a free-association test. Freud argued that the apparent correlation between this set of ideas and worry over the former companion's potential pregnancy was not haphazard coincidence.

Even so, though this distinction is important, we must leave room for the possibility of a merger between such unconscious conflicts and synchronicity events. In fact, our model of perception actually predicts that such mergers will be rather routine.

Both Jung and Koestler were influenced by Paul Kammerer, who published a book of carefully chronicled "meaningful coincidences."39x Kammerer, reports Koestler, regarded "random coincidence" as a false representation and that actually there is a universal, but mostly unnoticed except in unusual cases, "recurrence of identical or similar data in contiguous areas of space or time." Kammerer regarded this "simple empirical fact" as furthering his arguments in favor of Lamarckism, the rival theory of Darwinism that says that heredity is influenced by the specific behaviors of parents.39Ax

Kammerer posited a "law of seriality" that ensures that "acausally related" events stream together. Koestler notes that the chief difference between Kammerer and Jung is that Jung is more concerned with serial events and Jung with simultaneous events. In fact, Jung seems to have expanded on the idea of synchronicity to cover paranormal phenomena in general. Synchronicity is to him a linchpin of the collective unconscious, that vast storehouse of archetypes (symbols common to humankind throughout history).

Kammerer's credibility is however at issue. He committed suicide in 1926 after his specimen that supposedly bolstered Lamarckism was exposed as having been doctored, though Koestler argued that Nazis or Nazi-types sabotaged the sample as a means of discrediting Kammerer's socialist views.

Both Jung and Koestler cited the work of J.B. Rhine and Rhine's successor, physicist Helmut Schmidt, in support of their ideas. More recently, Josephson has cited telepathy studies and argued that unfair methods have been used to discredit their value.

As Leonard Mlodinow38x points out, if a telepathy test is given to a number of people, it would be expected that at least one person would do well enough to vary substantially from the mean. Still, I would add that if that same individual repeated such a "fluke" with more than one trial set, then one would strongly suspect a non-random force was at work.

(Again, in our model, randomness is in part a consequence of the aperiodicity of the rich composite reality signal or subsignals. The computational difficulty of predicting a specific subsignal is, like weather prediction, of a high order. What this has to do with the "true randomness" of particle detection is a subject in need of considerably more work.)

Jung commented that in one Rhine study, subjects did well on the initial trial, when they were interested in what was going on, but afterward their returns were no better than random. I don't have the Rhine study at hand and so I cannot say whether the initial variance was statistically reasonable. Yet, based on our model, we would say that a subject's reality construction is heavily dependent on focus. In our scenario, a high level of belief might affect outcome.

I well recollect the day that I reached a friend via cellphone, having been momentarily convinced that I had rung up the correct number. As he was answering his only home phone, I suddenly realized I had dialed the wrong number -- and the connection became weak in phase with my doubt. After breaking contact, I checked carefully and found that I had indeed dialed a wrong number. I hasten to add that usually when I make a mistake, convinced or not, nothing atypical happens.

[See Appendix A for an anecdotal collection of strange events.]

Of course some of Jung's synchronicities are quite easily dismissed as typical of randomness, such as his observation of "surnames that fit" a person's vocation or disposition. That said, how does one account -- assuming Jung's truthfulness -- for his "fish story"?

In his Synchronicity paper, Jung noted that on April 1, 1949, a Friday, "we had fish for lunch" and someone mentioned the custom of "making an 'April fish' of someone." That morning, he had made a note of an inscription reading "Est homo totus medius piscis ab imo." That afternoon, a former patient, who he hadn't seen in months, showed him "extremely impressive" pictures of fish that she had painted since he'd last seen her. In the evening, "I was shown a piece of embroidery with fish-like sea monsters on it" and the following morning another patient, who he hadn't seen for years, told of a dream in which she stood on the shore of a lake and saw a large fish that swam straight toward her and landed at her feet."

True, one might argue that, because he is seeking associations, he is noticing associations that occur routinely but tend to go unnoticed by most people who have learned, correctly, to relegate such pairings to "background noise." But it is relevant from our viewpoint that at the time "I was engaged in the study of the fish symbol in history." The focus on fish patterns influenced his reality construction, is how we would put it.

To drive home that point, we cite this footnote by Jung: "As`a pendant to what I have said above, I should liken to mention that I wrote these lines sitting by the lake. Just as I finished this sentence, I walked over to the sea wall and there lay a dead fish, about a foot long, apparently uninjured..."

Jung credits the astronomer Camille Flammarion with this anecdote40x: "A certain M. Deschamps, when a boy in Orleans, was once given a piece of plum pudding by a M. de Fortgibu. Ten years later he discovered another plum pudding in a Paris restaurant and asked if he could have a piece. It turned out, however, that the plum pudding was already ordered -- by M. de Fortgibu. Many years afterwards M. Deschamps was invited to partake of a plum pudding as a special rarity. While he was eating it he remarked that the only thing lacking was M. de Fortgibu. At that moment the door opened and an old, old man in the late stages of disorientation walked in: M. de Fortgibu, who had got hold of the wrong address and burst in on the party by mistake."

Though this story can't be verified, it is illustrative of "common knowledge." Many people have experienced "synchronicities" of this sort, sometimes equally dramatic. Yet, such happenings are usually relegated to private life and "laughed off."

Jung's journey in psychology was from the beginning interwoven with a keen interest in paranormal phenomena, which he tried to explain in terms of deep forces to which the individual's unconscious was connected. "Ghost stories and spirit-like phenomena practically never prove what they seem to," he wrote in a 1950 note2y. "They provide information about things the layman knows nothing of, such as the exteriorization of unconscious processes (my emphasis).

Jung's observations led him to believe that bizarre occurrences appear to be projections of unconscious forces within an affected individual. What we have been saying is that bizarre occurrences may indeed point to mental activity, but that the perception-phenomenon feedback mechanism applies to all detected events.

There are a number of types of events that go under the heading paranormal phenomena. I make no effort to list them all, though I would say that we are talking about some type of non-material medium that links minds. Individual reality construction is heavily influenced by the reality weaving of other minds, so that no individual has control of his or her own mind or reality flow.

Various religious systems recognize this "below-the-radar" connectivity but that does not imply that a specific system is particularly helpful to the individual. Superstition has an impact on reality formation. If a person is taught to believe -- even partly -- a particular superstition, a person's reality formulator may warp in some "bad luck event" in the near future. In this regard, consider the remarkable discovery that an asteroid, Apophis, has been discovered that is expected to make a very close flyby on April 13th, 2029, a Friday, where it will pass to within 5 Earth diameters of us (below the altitude of geosynchronous satellites). The exact path the asteroid follows on its flyby in 2029 will determine whether it smashes into the Earth seven years later -- on April 13, 2036, another Friday.

Modern American popular culture, of course, has taken up the notion that Friday the 13th is a bad luck day. Moreover, there has been greatly increased awareness of the possibility of an asteroid strike, stimulated by a number of films.

So shall we assume that the Friday the 13th dates stem from routine statistical coincidence, or is it possible that popular fears and expectations have somehow been projected to weave mass fantasies and fears into a dreamscape that "solidifies" into "concrete reality"?

The gist of my theological views may be found at my blog
Zion Calling
https://zion78.blogspot.com/

Consider the word enchantment. The root is the word chant. It seems plausible that chanting could influence an individual or communal dreamweaver by the wave entrainment effect. Smaller signals tend to fall in line and the later reality signal has a high degree of coherence. The word is associated with magic spells (as in incantation) and with modern rhythmic music. It could well be that not only can a musical number put one into a trance-like reverie, but actually alter the output reality signal.

Recall the traditional Irish bards, who were not only poets but considered to be powerful magicians (although that element was played down after Catholicism took hold).

The placebo effect has been thoroughly documented and some scientists might hold that some miraculous cures are a close cousin of that effect. I would agree that the power of belief can strongly affect an individual's recovery. But I would add that if another mind is sharing with the patient that belief, the joint reality formulation may be stronger (or weaker). Yet who has the kind of belief that makes the lame leap and the blind see? Who has the power of belief to raise the dead?

Such biblical feats are often seen as nothing more than comic book stuff. But, if consciousness interacts with a dreamlike signal, then such story changes aren't impossible. Even so, they would require a level of belief that many would consider superhuman.
Sometimes knowledge of reality reformulation is not beneficial. Individuals may have learned various manipulations to adversely affect the reality streams of others, though this would tend to imply that their own reality stream would be likewise adversely affected.

And aside from such manipulators, there are also the charlatans and confidence tricksters who are adept at deceiving people via ordinary, sense-moderated illusions and delusions.

At any rate, the ideas stated above are meant to indicate a much more malleable form of reality than previously held in science and are not meant to lure the unwary into treacherous territory.


Footnotes:
Apologies that the footnotes are not in precise order and for the somewhat erratic footnote code. Yet, the reader should have little difficulty.



1. Quoted in Arthur Koestler's October the First Is Too Late (1966)
2. The Discoverers by Alan Lightman (Pantheon/Random House 2005)
3. Quoted in N.G. Vankampen's paper Information, physics, quantum: the search for links in Feynman and Computation , edited by Anthony J.G. Hey (Westview Press 1999)
3a. Geons, Black Holes & Quantum Foam: A Life in Physics by John Archibald Wheeler with Kenneth Ford (W.W. Norton 1998).
3b. For a comprehensive approach to the subtleties of the issue of time, see The Labyrinth of Time by Michael Lockwood (Oxford, 2009).
4. About Time: Einstein's Unfinished Revolution by Paul Davies (Touchstone/Simon & Schuster 1996)
5. Where Does the Weirdness Go? by David Lindley (Basic Books 1996).
6. The New Quantum Universe by Tony Hey and Patrick Walters (Cambridge 2003)
6a. Quoted in The Ghost in the Atom, P.C.W. Davies and J.R. Brown (Cambridge 1986, revised 1999). The book is based on a series of BBC interviews with quantum physicists concerning the measurement problem and Aspect's results.
7. Quantum Reality: Beyond the New Physics by Nick Herbert (Anchor/Random House 1985)
8. Two Kinds of Reality by Eugene Wigner, an article first published in the philosophical journal The Monist in 1964
8a. For a thorough examination of the Copenhagen interpretation, see The Non-Local Universe: the New Physics of Matters of the Mind by Robert Nadeau and Menas Kafatos (Oxford, 1999).
8b. See The Intelligent Universe: a new view of creation and evolution (Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1983) by Fred Hoyle. In this book, written near the end of his life, Hoyle proposed a "panspermia" theory whereby microbial life and viruses travel through space and rain on the earth. At first blush implausible, but he is quite persuasive on these points. He is attempting to account for the astounding improbability of life spontaneously generating on any one planet.
9. The Cosmic Landscape by Leonard Susskind (Back Bay/Little Brown 2006)
10. Landauer's paper Information is Inevitably Physical was printed in Feynman and Computation, op cit.
11. Wholeness and the Implicate Order by David Bohm (Rutledge & Kegan Paul 1980)
12. Visual Intelligence: How We Create What We See by Donald Hoffman (W.W. Norton 1998); Hoffman and two colleagues wrote a paper on observer-based mechanics, which is available via his home page.
1x. Whether the manufacture occurs before or after the fact is the bone of contention.
2x. One idea for recording an emotion value would be to use z = x +iy, with x representing the pain level and y the pleasure; the i is largely for bookkeeping convenience. We would write the emotion ratio as iy/x and the conflict, or tension, magnitude as |z| = (x2+y2)1/2. So |z|iy/x would give a complete emotion value.
3x.The brain must employ noise detection routines and error-correction algorithms. We would then expect that it generally filters out 1/f noise, which is essentially ubiquitous for natural processes, while scanning for meaningful signals. It may perhaps also filter white noise.
Also, noise being the complement of the meaningful signal, it is vaguely conceivable that the brain might mimic regression analysis to determine whether a set of wave forms shows meaningful correlation. If so, the brain might use this technique to hunt for a threat or reward without knowing exactly what it's looking for. I am not however aware of any indication the brain uses such a method. Habituation versus sensitization tend to determine threat or attraction level.
Fear of the unknown, of course, is a useful evolutionary adaptation. Hence a major brain task is to sift noise in search of a null result, checking for noise that differs from background noise. The signal might only be meaningful because it doesn't fit any template including the template for background noise.
4x. I use the term prime directive as a shortcut syntactical device. Likewise for such terms as hope and decision.
5x. One wonders how natural selection selected natural selection.
6x. The low entropy process of doing science permits recovery of some of this undetected information, and we might see scientific endeavor as a consequence of an organismic drive to be aware of new threats and opportunities. But I have no desire to overstate the case for Darwinism, which, I believe, is valid within its parameters, just as are other scientific theories but which, as with any theory, cannot be used to cover all bases.
6xa. I have not gone into details of control theory. My use of complex numbers for the emotion value should not be confused with the z-transform that converts a discrete time domain signal -- sequence of real numbers -- into a complex frequency domain representation. This conceptual paper does not delve into engineering specifics.
7x. The slaughter of World War I stirred Freud to alter his psychodynamic theory to posit a psychic force he called thanatos, or primitive death wish. My thinking is that the so-called death wish is in fact what Freud might have called the ego's struggle to suppress ("kill") the superego, whereby infantile unconscious desires can be given free reign. The desire to use intoxicants shows this tendency. When individual minds get subsumed by a mob frenzy, something of the sort is going on. Others are permitting and encouraging the venting of infantile needs so the individual is glad to enroll. It is only one step from mob psychology to the manipulation of unconscious needs by skillful, perhaps jingoistic, propagandists.
8x. Of course the Vulcans were inhuman. Also, at special periods they went through ferocious primitive emotionalism.
9x. We can talk about the mechanics of consciousness without being able to define its kernel. Though I think that Roger Penrose was technically in error with his Goedel self-referencing argument in The Emperor's New Mind, I agree that there is a problem in coming to terms with the actuality of consciousness. It seems more than an epiphenomenon. That a quantum theory of gravity would clear that matter up seems a bit strange to me, but Penrose should be given great credit for plowing a lot of ground that others have avoided.
10x. Also, the subjective sense of passage of time varies with level of alertness and the E-value of the experience.
11x. Again, the mechanics can be described but the actual conscious cognition escapes obvious comprehension.
12x. Visual Intelligence: How We Create What We See by Donald D. Hoffman (W.W. Norton 1998). Observer Mechanics by cognitive psychologist Hoffman and two colleagues is advertised on Hoffman's home page.
13x. David Deutsch, in Fabric of Reality: The Science of Parallel Universes and Its Implications (Allen Lane/Penguin 1997), does discuss the concept in a serious way. John Wheeler, who favors a participatory universe interpretation nevertheless seems to shy away from a virtual reality model.
14x. The Synaptic Self by Joseph Le Doux (Viking 2002)
15x. Dennett's Consciousness Explained (Little, Brown 1991) offers some valid criticisms of what he calls "the Cartesian theater" model of consciousness. In my reading of his book, I did not notice any jarring contradictions between his points and mine. Even so, he seems to be on a crusade to banish the soul or "the ghost in the machine" by emphasizing emergence and process. I don't think he achieved that goal. As for me, I simply avoid the issue of whether or not there is such a vitalistic force and instead focus on the process.
16x. But I hasten to warn that devices that give the illusion of a voice or other sound originating inside one's own head pose a serious risk of unethical use.
17x. In Search of Memory: The Emergence of a New Science of Mind by Eric Kandel(W.W. Norton 2007)
18x. The Psychology of Consciousness by G. William Farthing (Prentice Hall 1992)
19x. It would seem that free will would require some superhuman influence. But even Christian tradition says that unregenerate persons are controlled by Satan, the father of lies. In this view, only a person who partakes of God's spirit is set free, with freedom of choice presumably improving over time.
20x. Sync: How Order Emerges from Chaos in the Universe, Nature and Daily Life by Steven Strogatz (Hyperion 2003).
21x. A Brief Tour of Human Consciousness by V.S. Ramachandran (Pi Press 2004)
22x. Though I doubt the brain's processor uses anything as sophisticated as the least squares method.
24x. This conjecture may not account for all cases.
25x. See for example Witness by Whittaker Chambers (Regnery 1952).
26x. Coincidence, Chaos, and All that Math Jazz by Edward B. Burger and Michael Starbird(W.W. Norton 2005)
27xa. See Strogatz op cit; Order Out of Chaos: Man's Dialogue with Nature by Ilya Prigogine and Isabelle Stengers (Bantam 1984); and Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution by Stuart A. Kauffman (Oxford 1993).
27x. 13: The Story of the World's Most Popular Superstition by Nathaniel Lachenmeyer (Avalon 2004).
28x. An example of such opportunism is Incredible Coincidence: The Baffling World of Synchronicity by "psychic researcher" Alan Vaughan (J.B. Lippincott 1979).
29x. The Quark and the Jaguar: Adventures in the Simple and Complex by Murray Gell-Mann (Macmillan 1995). I am unsure of what is meant by a "goblin world."
30x. Quoted in Ghost op cit.
31x. The Roots of Coincidence by Arthur Koestler (Hutchinson Publishing Group 1972, Random House 1973).
31xa. Synchronicity: the Bridge Between Matter and Mind by F. David Peat (Bantam 1987)
32x. Jordan's paper, Positivistische Bemerbungen uber die parapsychischen Erscheinungen (Zentralblatt fur Psychotherapie [Leipzig] IX [1936] 14ff) was cited in The basic writings of Carl Jung, Violet Staub Laszlo, ed (Modern Library 1993 edition, page 129).
33x. Cited in A life of Jung by Ronald Hayman (W.W. Norton 1999).
34x. A Life of Jung op cit.
35x. "Beyond Materialism," an essay printed in Bricks to Babel by Arthur Koestler (Hutchinson Publishing Group 1980).
36xa. Synchronicity: An Acausal Connecting Principle by Jung and Archetypischer Vorstellungen auf die Bildung Naturwissenchafltlicher Theorem bei Kepler (The archetype in Keplerian physics) by Wolfgang Pauli, which appeared in Naturerklarung und Psyche 1952. A corrected version of Jung's article appears in Collected works of C.G. Jung translated by R.F.C. Hull (Bollingen Foundation/Princeton University Press 1960).
36xb. Having not read Pauli's paper and despite Jung's coy hints, I am uncertain how far Pauli was willing to go publicly in committing himself to a quantum aspect to paranormal phenomena.
37x. Uncertainty, the Life and Science of Werner Heisenberg by David Cassidy (W.H. Freeman 1992).
38x. The Drunkard's Walk: How Randomness Rules Our lives by Leonard Mlodinow (Random House 2008)
39x. Das Gesetz der Serie by Paul Kammerer, cited by Koestler. Einstein reportedly said of Kammerer's logbook of some 100 selected examples of bizarre coincidences that it was "original and by no means absurd" but then Einstein was known for being courteous to eccentrics.
39ax. Kammerer's idea is echoed later by Rupert Sheldrake's morphogenetic field.
40x. Jung is quoting directly from Flammarion's book The Unknown which came out in 1900. Flammarion (1842-1925) was an astronomer who sold many books promoting his conjectures about life on other planets. Though his specific conjectures have been nullified by modern space science, many in the scientific community agree with the essential notion that life on other planets is quite likely. Flammarion however also believed that "spiritism" -- today called paranormal phenomena -- should be investigated in a scientific manner.
41. Aphorisms of old may well correspond to modern insight. Jeremiah 17:8-10 says, "The heart is deceitful above all things, and desperately wicked: who can know it?" What is that but a description of how the unconscious operates? We would interpret "desperately wicked" to mean very ill, or the software programing is badly snarled. What can right the tangle?
P1. Niels Bohr's Times by Abraham Pais (Carendon Press, Oxford 1991). For an explanation of complementarity, Pais recommends Bohr's article that appeared in Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist (1949), edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp.
P2. Quoted by A. Petersen, Bulletin of Atomic Scientists, Sept. 63, Page 8, and cited by Pais (above).
g. Goedel's position and Einstein'e response are found in Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, Paul Arthur Schilpp, editor, 1949.
e. The Bohr, Born and Pauli essays are found in Schilpp, along with Einstein's reply.
1y. Quoted by Koestler in Roots, who was citing a passage from Jeans' Rede Lectures.
2y. Foreward to the book Spuk: irrglaube oder wahrgraube (Ghosts: false belief or true?) by Fanny Moser. The foreward is found in Jung's collected works translated by R.F.C. Hull (Bollingen).
zz1. One reference among many possible: A Short History of Philosophy by Robert C. Solomon and Kathleen Higgins (Oxford 1996). Solomon was a specialist in Hegel and his contemporaries.
zz2. The Analysis of Matter by Bertrand Russell (Allen and Unwin 1927).
Edited version posted July 1, 2009; I will update this page from time to time.
Material on Goedel and Einstein has been corrected as of Dec. 9, 2009. Complementarity matter has been added as of Nov. 18, 2009 and updated as of Dec. 9, 2009.
Updates concerning Koestler were added Oct. 30, 2010. Minor updates have continued through Feb. 19, 2018.
Consider using a free web page monitoring service, such as ChangeDetection.com, to keep tabs on revisions of this page.

<i><U>What is a continuum? </u></i><br />Russell knocks Hegel's logic (1903)

Bertrand Russell, in his Principles of Mathematics (1903), comments on G.W. Hegel's Logic : 271. The notion of continuity has be...